The Guiding Principles were endorsed by the U.N. Human Rights Council in June, 2011. “In an unprecedented step, the United Nations Human Rights Council has endorsed a new set of Guiding Principles for Business and Human Rights designed to provide -for the first time- a global standard for preventing and addressing the risk of adverse impacts on human rights linked to business activity.” United Nations Human Rights Council, News Release, New Guiding Principles on Business and human rights endorsed by the UN Human Rights Council, 16 June 2011.
The consideration of the Guiding Principles marks a great milestone in
the development of frameworks of governance of economic actors outside
of the framework of national law. This milestone can be understood as
consisting of four great aspects. The Guiding Principles represents the
first successful efforts to provide a governance framework that can be
adopted into the national legal orders of adhering states. In this
aspect it represents a critical effort in the harmonization of national
law on the basis of global consensus. At the same time, the Guiding
Principles also represents the first successful effort to provide a
framework for the development of customary and conventional
international law. In this aspect, the Guiding principles represent a
critical effort in the harmonization of governance for an important
transnational actor at the international level. Additionally, the
Guiding Principles for the first time acknowledges the existence and
importance of non-governmental sources of governance rules. The embrace
of the importance of social norm systems of autonomous behavior rules
for economic enterprises represents a critical acknowledgment of
non-state actors as a source of norm making the authority of which is
not dependent on states. Lastly, the Guidelines for the first time link
remedial obligations to the state duty to remedy and the corporate
responsibility to respect human rights in a way that both preserves the
autonomy of human rights and their connection to both law and social
norms systems.
The Guiding Principles will likely be significantly influential not just as a source of soft law principles at the international level, but as a basis for the evolution of common understanding of appropriate standards of corporate behavior for the development of social norms and eventually changes to the form of the domestic legal orders of states. It will be inevitable that as the Guidelines move toward approval and implementation after endorsement, all major stakeholders in the process will seek to mold the Guidelines to suit their interests. See, e.g., Stefan Marculewicz, U.N. Special Representative's Final Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights: Policy Implications for Employers, Global Employment Law, March 29, 2011 ("We also believe these Guiding Principles, if not addressed proactively by companies, may create an opportunity for advocacy organizations (such as issue-specific non-governmental organizations and labor unions) to seek to define the parameters of the Guiding Principles on their own terms. "). These discussions will draw on the Guiding Principles themselves and their inevitable comparison with failed earlier efforts to provide a structure for the governance of business actions with human rights impacts. John Knox, The Human Rights Council Endorses “Guiding Principles” for Corporations ASIL Insights Aug. 1, 2011 ("In the wake of the debate over the Draft Norms, the appointment of John Ruggie was something of a gamble that he could bring consensus out of the controversy over the application of human rights principles to corporations. To a remarkable degree, he did so. The Human Rights Council’s endorsement of the Guiding Principles opens a new chapter in the continuing effort to bring human rights law to bear on corporations. It remains to be seen, however, how successful the Guiding Principles will eventually prove at curbing corporate abuses of human rights.").
The Guiding Principles will likely be significantly influential not just as a source of soft law principles at the international level, but as a basis for the evolution of common understanding of appropriate standards of corporate behavior for the development of social norms and eventually changes to the form of the domestic legal orders of states. It will be inevitable that as the Guidelines move toward approval and implementation after endorsement, all major stakeholders in the process will seek to mold the Guidelines to suit their interests. See, e.g., Stefan Marculewicz, U.N. Special Representative's Final Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights: Policy Implications for Employers, Global Employment Law, March 29, 2011 ("We also believe these Guiding Principles, if not addressed proactively by companies, may create an opportunity for advocacy organizations (such as issue-specific non-governmental organizations and labor unions) to seek to define the parameters of the Guiding Principles on their own terms. "). These discussions will draw on the Guiding Principles themselves and their inevitable comparison with failed earlier efforts to provide a structure for the governance of business actions with human rights impacts. John Knox, The Human Rights Council Endorses “Guiding Principles” for Corporations ASIL Insights Aug. 1, 2011 ("In the wake of the debate over the Draft Norms, the appointment of John Ruggie was something of a gamble that he could bring consensus out of the controversy over the application of human rights principles to corporations. To a remarkable degree, he did so. The Human Rights Council’s endorsement of the Guiding Principles opens a new chapter in the continuing effort to bring human rights law to bear on corporations. It remains to be seen, however, how successful the Guiding Principles will eventually prove at curbing corporate abuses of human rights.").
In order to better understand the Guidelines, it may be useful to
examine the context in which the Guiding Principles were developed and
the development of the Guiding Principles from draft (in November 2010)
to final form
(March 2011, the DP or "Draft Principles") from a more neutral
perspective. For this purpose I have provided my own thoughts about
that context and development. That analysis is divided into several
parts:
Part I: From Conception to Principle—The development of the Protect-Respect-Remedy Framework and the Drafting of the Guiding Principles (April 24, 2011);
Part II. The Draft Guiding Principles: Section by Section Analysis (April 30, 2011);
Part III. Justification and Legitimacy in the Introduction to the Guiding Principles Implementing the UN "Protect, Respect and Remedy" Framework.
Part IV. Section By Section Analysis, From Draft to Final Principles: Overall Structure and Capstone Principles.
Part V. Section By Section Analysis: The State Duty to Protect Principles.
Part VI. Section By Section Analysis: The Corporate Responsibility to Respect.
Part VII. Section By Section Analysis: The Obligation to Remedy.
Part VIII. The General Principles: A Preliminary Assessment.
This posting ends the series with a preliminary assessment of the Guiding Principles in the context of the "Protect, Respect, and Remedy" framework so well constructed by John Ruggie and his team.
The full analysis will be published as Backer, Larry Catá, From Institutional Misalignment to Socially Sustainable Governance: The Guiding Principles for the Implementation of the United Nation’s 'Protect, Respect and Remedy' and the Construction of Inter-Systemic Global Governance (September 5, 2011). Pacific McGeorge Global Business & Development Law Journal, 2011 and can be accessed here.
(From Marcy Murningham, Human Rights Due Diligence, The Murningham Post 16 Aug. 2010)
_________________________________
The GP: A Preliminary Assessment
Principled Pragmatism and the
Limits of Formal Innovation.
The great challenge of the 21st
century is that of the institutionalization of the system of globalization that
emerged in the last decades of the 20th century. The SRSG astutely explained that the issue of
business and human rights is a microcosm of that challenge.[1] A number of those challenges remain pointed
and unresolved in the framing architecture of the GP. This section examines a number of the more
significant issues that are either raised by or remain unresolved in the
GP. The section also suggests the
potentially significant institutional effects of the framework on the
relationships between the state, the international community, and business in
the context of globalization.
1. The Dilemmas of the Law-State
System in a Global Context. The
SRSG’s GP principles outlining the extent of the state duty to protect human
rights raises a number of challenges that reflect both the difficulties of
moving forward the contemporary culture of the law-state system and the
conundrums of building a system on an acceptance of the basic assumptions on
which that law-state system is built.
GP Principle 1 nicely
suggests the difficulties. On its face
it suggests the obvious—that states are required to abide by their obligations
under international law, whether they are obligations specifically undertaken
pursuant to conventional law or treaty, or whether they are part of the complex
of obligations understood as customary international law. But there is the problem. First, the state of customary international
law remains contested. Some believe that
customary international law does not exist.[2]
Others believe that some elements of customary international law is binding
even on rejecting states, and that such binding customary norms, in the form of
jus cogens,[3]
can be the subject of international tribunals.[4] Second, many states apply the logic of their
law system to substantially narrow the legal effect of both customary and
conventional law within their territories.
Many states talk the position that conventional law applies to them only
to the extent that they have agreed to be bound. In some jurisdictions that agreement to be
bound is itself ineffective unless the legislative body actually incorporates
the convention’s obligations into the domestic legal order.[5]
Additionally, even where a state agrees to be bound, it may condition that
agreement on any number of reservations, the legal effects of which are still a
subject of lively academic debate.[6] Most importantly, as a matter of law,
international instruments that are neither treaties nor conventional law are
not, strictly speaking, legally binding on states. Lastly, in the absence of a legitimate
interpretative body, it is sometimes difficult to develop a consensus on the interpretation
of treaties or conventions, or their application in specific
circumstances. The International Court
of Justice[7]
is sometimes of help, but its jurisdiction is also limited and to some extent
optional.[8]
The limitations ultimately
written into GP Principle 1 might be understood by drawing a parallel to the
governance framework of the European Union. This tension is better understood
in two parts. First, the tension can be
understood as one touching on the supremacy of international law over
incompatible domestic legal measures.
The second, and more difficult tension, can be understood as touching on
the supremacy of international law (and its human rights obligations) over incompatible
provisions of domestic constitutional law.
The issue of the supremacy of Community Law over incompatible
domestic law has over a long period of time tended to be accepted as a basic
feature of membership within the E.U.
In many Member States, the principle of the supremacy of Community law
is accepted as a matter of domestic constitutional law as well--at least with
respect to incompatible national legislation.
In some cases, the Member States have re-constructed their
constitutional orders to explicitly accommodate Community Law Supremacy.
But, the issue of the nature and extent of the primacy of
Community law within the European Union, especially where such primacy may
contravene basic principles of the constitutional order of a Member State has
proven a difficult one in theory. Member States appear to reserve to themselves
an authority to judge the extent of that authority, especially where it might
affect the fundamental sovereign character of the state, or the basic human
rights and organizational provisions of its constitutional order. Most
famously, perhaps, the Irish Supreme Court noted, "With regard to the
issue of the balance of convenience, I am satisfied that where an injunction is
sought to protect a constitutional right, the only matter which could be
properly capable of being weighed in a balance against the granting of such
protection would be another competing constitutional right." On the other hand it has proven to be
possible to sidestep these conceptual questions through the adoption of a
functional approach to the issue--combined with just in time amendments to
Member State constitutions or Treaty accommodation the constitutional
sensibilities of Member States.
But it is not clear that beyond the European Union and its deep
system of collaborative internationalism, states will be willing to read the
State duty to protect as importing an obligation to (at least in good faith)
accept the supremacy of international law generally, or more specifically European
against an incompatible provision of international law. Less likely is a willingness, as a matter of
constitutional policy, for states to commit to a policy of collaborative
constitutionalism requiring attempts a constitutional revision or
interpretation to ensure conformity with applicable international standards.
Another difficulty avoided
centers on the identification of the aggregate of obligations that constitute
applicable international human rights law.
The GP define “internationally recognized human rights” in a political
or sociological, or even cultural sense.
But then the Guidelines appear to hold only non-state actors—and principally
corporations—to that definition.[9] They are binding in those senses too. That binding effect is most prominently
important in connection with the development of social norm systems that affect
the corporate responsibility to respect human rights. It is also possible to assume that the
documents that constitute the International Bill of Human Rights serves as a
consensus generally of state obligations in a policy sense. But the International Bill of Rights does not
constitute a legally binding set of documents equally applicable to all states,
or even to all of the developed states.
As a legal rather than as a policy matter, the International Bill of Rights
may create some obligation, but may not obligate all states in the same way or
to the same extent. Those differences may serve as a basis for resistance by
states to specific applications of some or all parts of the International Bill of
Rights. It can also serve as a
significant point of friction if State A seeks to effectively impose the requisites
of International Bill of Rights on State
B through the extraterritorial application of the provisions on corporations
hosted in State B. Where the extraterritorial application can be contrary to
the constitutional norms of State B, the application of the GP become more
difficult. It is understandable, then, that the GP Principle 1 commentary
speaks of the state duty has legal and policy dimensions. Depending on the state, the balance between
the legal and policy pull of the International Bill of Rights that form the
core of the human rights obligations of states will vary considerably, and the
potentially different regimes of rights to which a company is subject while
operating in a host state can be even more pronounced. Indeed, unevenness in the recognition and
application of the International Bill of Rights by states will likely be the
norm, at least initially.
The extraterritorial
provisions, long supported by the SRSG,[10]
continues the dilemma of managing the leakage of state power into the borders
of other states within a system in which all states are ostensibly objects of
equal dignity and treatment. Extraterritorial application is a reasonable response
of high human rights value states to deficiencies in the incorporation of the
obligations of First Pillar duties in other states. And it may be reasonably grounded on an
extension of legal duties of the conduct of national corporate citizens when they
travel and engage in activities abroad.
The obligation is not for the benefit of the host state, but rather is
deemed to be essential to the internal ordering of the state and the management
of the conduct of its citizens. Yet to
some extent, extraterritoriality of this sort also smacks of "status"
legislation that has tended to be disfavored in the modern era within constitutional
systems like that of the United States.
The SRSG suggests that extraterritorial projects of human rights duties
"can provide much-needed support to host States that lack the capacity to
implement fully an effective regulatory environment on their own." However, extraterritorial application of
home state law can easily be (mis?)characterized as indirect projections of state
power abroad. When such projections are
directed at states with a history of colonial rule, sensitivities may make such
projections not merely unpopular but unlawful within the territory of the host
state. Yet the neo colonialist argument
has been used selectively. It is easily
applied to former colonial powers asserting extraterritorial powers, but tends
to be overlooked when the projecting power is a state that can style itself as
still "developing." The SRSG has noted that the issue of the lawfulness
of extraterritorial legislation remains unsettled as a matter of international
law. Where the State itself is engaged
in business abroad, the SRSG suggests that there are "strong policy
reasons for home States to encourage their companies to respect rights
abroad. And indeed one might suggest
that in those cases the State duty to protect necessarily embraces all state
activities domestically and elsewhere and in whatever form conducted.
One of the great markers of
globalization is the change in the nature of the power of the state—still
powerful but now more ambiguous both within its own territory and projected
onto the territory of other states. The GP
look both forward and backward on the issue of state power. On the one hand, the GP continue to encourage
the extraterritorial application of state power. Though the encouragement is permissive,[11]
two distinct and not necessarily positive actions are encouraged. The first is the encouragement of the
traditional system of subordination that marked the relationship (and the state
system itself) between states from the 19th century.[12] Under CG Principle 2, strong and rich states
will be encouraged to project their power through the businesses they control
within the states in which those corporations operate.[13] Companies will be encouraged as well—not to
look to compliance with the law of the host state, but rather to look to
compliance with the law of the home state.
One effect is positive in a sense, such encouragement will create incentives
for harmonization of law by encouraging host states to conform their domestic
law to that of home states with significant corporate activity in their
territory. But the other effect might be
less positive—especially in weak governance zones—the effect might be to
encourage the transfer of the functions of the law state form the host to the
home state. Rather than encourage the
development of stronger or better government in the host state, the power of
extraterritoriality might be to transfer that power to the outside regulating
states, whose values, laws and courts would substitute for that of the host
state. This could deepen weak governance
rather than encourage the development of stronger government in weak governance
zones.
2. The law-policy conundrum of
the state duty to protect. The issue
of the scope of human rights norms, and the differences between the first
pillar’s legalism and the second pillar’s functionalist internationalism,
highlights another tension within the state duty to protect pillar—that between
state legal and policy obligations. That
tension mimics, to some extent, those between the formal law systems context of
the state duty and the functionalist social norm based context of corporate
governance rules. The GP distinguish
between the narrow formalism of legal constraints and the open-ended
possibilities of policy considerations.
It serves, in the latter respect, to provide suggestions and best
practices as a means of helping shape the universe of permissible responses to
policy issues touching on the regulation of business and human rights without
appearing to mandate this approach. The
idea appears to be to set the stage for an organic growth of right conduct and
policy without appearing to manage that movement.
It follows that one of the
great innovations of the Guiding Principles is its recognition that states
operate on two levels, both of which having some governance effects. The first is the most traditional and well
understood—the legal obligations of states both internally with respect to the
organization and application of its domestic legal order, and externally with
respect to the obligations of states under international law. The second is less well known and its role in
managing conduct much more disputed in the conventional literature—the
regulatory effects of state policy.
While this second form of regulatory regime is beginning to be better
manifested, for example in the operation of large sovereign wealth funds,[14] it is not usually the object of operationalization
precisely because it is not law/regulation and thus is not usually considered a
legitimate source of state action that affects the conduct of the state and
others. But the recognition of the
policy obligations of states produces issues which are to some extent
unavoidable.
3. Character
of the Guidelines: Framework, Handbook, Roadmap or Law? Soon after the draft Guidelines were
announced, Dr Peter Davis is Ethical
Corporation’s politics editor published an opinion piece that characterized
the GP as a handbook.[15]
It is not clear that Dr. Davis is
correct, but the point he raises is critically important for the evolution of
the Guiding Principles as they move from acceptance toward implementation. Unless individuals can agree on the manner in
which the Guiding Principles are to be read, the possibility of fragmentation
in interpretation, even at the most fundamental level, remains quite
likely. That fracture is most likely to
mirror the fractures in approaches to law and law interpretation between law
systems that are still open to custom and organic growth through application,
and those who approach the Guiding Principles like a Code—a self contained and
internally self referencing system that defines the entire possible universe of
interpretive possibility within its provisions, more or less. The former would evolve through deductive
reasoning principles grounded in the aggregation of application of the Guiding
Principles in state judicial and non-juridical for a, business grievance
structures to the extent they are reported, policy reactions, and the work of
international organs applying their related soft law frameworks which
incorporate the Guiding Principles. The latter would deepen the implications of
the formal construction of the Guiding Principles as Code—using its
hierarchically arranged principles structure as the basis through which it can
be applied in particular context without thereby moving beyond the parameters
of the Guiding Principles themselves as the sole legitimate source of rules.
The former can tolerate a considerable degree of difference in result in
interpretation—certainly one of the permissible outcomes implicitly suggested
in the Guiding Principles Commentary. The later will require something like the
institutionalized interpretive structure of the European Court of Justice
system[16]
to retain a stronger hand in the interpretive growth of the Guiding
Principles. The choice of the language
of interpretation will have profound effects on the culture of application.[17]
It is understood why the SRSG did not
wade into those institutionalizing waters.
Yet the manner of institutionalization and guidance will be critical to
the success of the Guiding Principles.
One of the great projects that await those who would move the Guiding
Principles from document to applied governance will be to gain a measure of
control over the process of its application.
At some point it will be necessary
to order this heterodox and polycentric operation—not necessarily to unify it,
but to ensure substantial coordination with a necessary flexibility.
4. The Character of Corporate Law Making. The heart of
the corporate responsibility to respect human rights is human rights due
diligence. In the hands of the SRSG and
as memorialized in the Guiding Principles, human rights due diligence is
drafted into multiple service. In one
sense, human rights due diligence, as the regularization of policy serves a
legislative function.[18] This suggests an alternative to the decades
long drift of corporate governance to the use of contract for regulatory
effect.[19] Second,
human rights due diligence serves an executive function, providing the
information be necessary for determining corporate action. Third, human rights due diligence also serves
as a monitoring device—for use by both internal and external stakeholders—to
make accountability more efficient. Lastly,
human rights due diligence serves a fact finding and remediation
function—providing the basis for both the process and substantive content of
resolving the consequences of human rights affecting actions. The SRSG makes clear that the principal
audience for these efforts is not the state but major corporate
stakeholders—customers, investors, local communities, labor, and others—who might
be affected by the human rights affecting activities of corporations.[20]
This is a consent-based system which is, in its own way, a reflection of the
more formalized notions of legitimacy and consent that frame modern Western
liberal constitutionalism.[21]
Human rights due diligence, then, organizes and constitutes, in institutional
form, a social norm system and makes it operative in a way that is attached to
but not completely dependent on the state and its law system. That system is
grounded in the logic of social norm system—constituted through and enforced by
the collective actions of those critical stakeholders participating in the
system itself, and based on disclosure.[22] But vesting so much into one process/product
may well overwhelm it. The regulation of
self regulation within a constraining international law normative field will
likely require further development as the effective realities of globalized
private governance itself continues to evolve.[23] This is consistent with the facts based
principled pragmatism on which the system itself is based, but one that
suggests a dynamic rather than a static element to the enterprise. Human rights due diligence will start off
fairly well defined—but the logic of its many purposes will tend to vastly
expand, and to some extent, distort the device.[24] At some point, and likely soon, the legislative,
administrative, monitoring and remediation functions of human rights due diligence
will have to be reframed and developed along the lines of the logic of
each.
A related issue touches on
the mechanics of human rights due diligence, and specifically the normative
effects of data gathering, a subject left substantially unexplored in the
Guiding Principles. This issue is most
dramatically drawn in the context of the early focus on gender inequalities and
the human rights regulation project of the Guiding Principles. Data collection, though, is hardly a
ministerial act. The choice of data suggests a normative privileging that
itself might legitimate emphasis in one area of human rights over others.
I have suggested the regulatory aspects of data collection in its guise as a
subset of surveillance. “Surveillance is one of the critical mechanisms of this
expansion of private power into what had been an exclusively public sphere.
Increasingly, public bodies are requiring, or permitting, private entities to
monitor and report on the conduct and activities of a host of actors. It has
also come to serve public bodies as a substitute for lawmaking. Surveillance is
a flexible engine.”[25] Surveillance has both domestic[26] and
transnational forms.[27]
“Together, surveillance in its various forms provides a unifying technique with
which governance can be effected across the boundaries of power fractures
without challenging formal regulatory power or its limits.”[28] As such, one could
understand this emphasis as suggesting a prioritization of gender issues in the
Second Pillar responsibility to respect.[29]
But the SRSG points to a more
benign function for data gathering. "Some have suggested that only
with disaggregated data can companies identify the relationship between gender
and their human rights impacts. It is not part of a company's baseline responsibility
to respect human rights to address the social formation of gender biases.
However, human rights due diligence should identify differential impacts based
on gender and consequently help companies avoid creating or exacerbating
existing gender biases."[30] The subtle distinction might at first be
startling – especially in an otherwise positive values based and behavior
modifying approach to corporate behavior. But closer reflection suggests
the strong connection between this position – that data be gathered to mind the
corporation's behavior but not that of the society in which the corporation
operates – and the foundational distinction between the legal rights regimes
peculiar to the First Pillar and the social rights regimes at the heart of the
corporate responsibility to respect human rights. This is made clearer by
the SRSG's explanation of the meaning of a multidimensional approach to gender
data. The multidimensional approach "means that human rights due
diligence should include examination of gender issues at multiple levels – for
example, the community (e.g. are women in a particular community allowed or expected
to work); and the society (e.g. is there institutionalized gender discrimination,
whether by law or religion)."
Issues of social
organization, and communal mores, including those touching on the status of
women, are matters for the state – and the First Pillar. Issues of corporate
involvement in issues touching on the status of women – as realized within corporate
operations – are matters at the heart of the Second Pillar. Those issues,
in that context, give rise to an autonomous set of responsibilities, the
touchstone of which is not necessarily dependent on the resolution of gender
status issues within a particular state. As such, data gathering and
analysis is critical for the production of corporate action that may lead to
treatment of women, and responses to concerns touching on the status and
treatment of women, within the corporation in ways that are distinct from those
presumed satisfactory elsewhere within the state in which a corporation
operates. The object is to control the behavior of corporations, not to
reform the social, political and legal structures of the states in which such
corporations operate. This is an especially important distinction in
cases where multinational corporations are operating within host states that
have a long history of colonialism and a strong sensitivity to interference
with sovereign prerogatives.
But this bifurcated approach
also produces a set of potentially necessary tensions. First, at its
limit, it may produce a situation where the corporate responsibility to respect
is inconsistent with the obligations imposed through host state law.[31] Second, the distinction between the
"social formation of gender biases" and "creating or
exacerbating existing gender biases" through corporate policy may be both
artificial and difficult to keep separate. Indeed, one recalls the
approach of the Sullivan Principles was to focus directly on corporate behavior
as a means of projecting social-cultural-and legal change into the host states
in which these principles were applied. "General Motors was the largest
employer of blacks in South Africa at that time, and Sullivan decided to use
his position on the Board of Directors to apply economic pressure to end the
unjust system. The result was the Sullivan Principles, which became the
blueprint for ending apartheid."[32] The successor Global
Sullivan Principles makes these connections explicit. The resulting
political program inherent in application of corporate second pillar
responsibilities may produce friction, especially if the methodological focus
is understood as containing a substantive element targeting the host
state. Lastly, the nature of gender rights remains highly
contested. This produces fracture, even in the approach to data
gathering. Consider, in this regard, the connection between the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights and the Cairo Declaration on Human Rights in
Islam. Their possible complementarity (or incompatibility) may
substantially direct both the methodological framework within which gender
issues are understood, and data harvested, as well as the analytics produced
therefrom.
5. The Problem of Double Character: State Owned Enterprises and Corporations
in Conflict Zones. The Guiding
Principles lend themselves well to the constrained complexity of simple
polycentricity—the coordination of law-state, social norm-corporate and
international systems. Where each
operates autonomously and within the logic or their organization, coordination
is possible and harmonization relatively easy to conceptualize if not
realize. But difficulties multiply where
institutions begin to act against type.
The problems of state owned enterprises and those of corporations
operating in the absence of an effective government test the Guiding Principles
as an integrated system. The Guiding
Principles acknowledge the problems but offer little but the state. This comes as something of a surprise.
In the context of corporate
activity in conflict-affected areas, the Guiding Principles[33]
tend to treat these entities the way international law treated states that were
not members of the Family of Nations before 1945.[34] In effect, in the absence of a local
government, the government of the host state can control the activities of the
corporation in the host state and thus control the effect of corporate economic
activity abroad.[35] But
it is hardly fitting for states in control of great corporate actors to use
those entities as the vehicle through which these states can project regulatory
and economic power outward. Multilateral
action would be more appropriate to avoid the appearance of domination and
incorporation.[36] That the Guiding Principles do not suggest
this as a baseline represents both a bow to reality (pragmatism)—states engage
in these activities and these regulatory projections with or without
permission. That it suggests that such
national projections of power be constrained by norms that have an
international component suggests a more subtle effort to manage national
activity within an international framework; but the tension remains.
In the context of state owned
enterprises, the Guiding Principles tend toward a divide and manage principle.[37] States are urged to take additional steps
when there is an ownership relationship between states and enterprises. States are reminded that such enterprises are
also subject to the obligations (including human rights due diligence
obligations) of the Second Pillar, but the formal distinction between state and
enterprise is preserved. This is an odd
result, particularly in the face of a the functionalism at the core of the
corporate responsibility to respect human rights that specifically eschews
legal constructions in the application of the Guidelines to business entities.[38] But that difference in approach suggests a
greater divergence—between the innate formalism of the state duty to protect
principles and the more functionalist corporate responsibility to respect
principles. That distinction, supported
by the reality of custom and behavior, however, produces tension when entities
straddle the state-corporate divide. A
different approach might have been more in accord with European approaches to
the issue of state involvement in economic activity, one which starts from the
position that state involvement in activity changes its character from private
to public. In this case, state owned
enterprises ought to be treated as both subject to the direct duty obligations
imposed on states and to the respect obligations that derives from their
organization as business enterprises.[39]
That this imposes potentially greater
obligations on state owned enterprises merely mirrors the advantages they can
also derive from that relationship unavailable to private enterprises.
6. Remedies.
The access to remedies provisions present the least autonomous and perhaps the
least robust link of the tightly integrated system that the Guiding Principle
represent. Between the initial
construction of the third pillar access to remedy of the “Protect, Respect and
Remedy” framework,[40]
and the final version of the Guiding Principles, the access to remedies prong
of the Guiding Principles became more an expression of the importance of the
state as a legitimating source of remediation.
This is not surprising, of course.
To some extent this movement is bound up with important ideological
foundations of Western notions of rule of law and the legitimate constitutional
order, both of which are deeply tied to the idea of an independent judiciary as
the critical component ion the protection of individual rights against others
and against the state.[41]
But that concept has less of a place where remediation also is meant to embrace
other governance systems providing individuals with a basis for complaint
grounded in norms other than the law of a particular state. There is a strong
nod in that direction in the General Principles,[42]
but these mechanisms are clearly meant to serve a marginal role—either to
prevent harm or to fill gaps. The
remediation workhorse remains the state and its judicial apparatus.
None of this is illogical;
and it reinforces conventional notions that were a strong element of the
critique of important sectors of the non-governmental organization community.[43]
But it tends to reduce the access to remedies to an instrumental application of
the consequences of the normative objectives of the state duty to protect and
the corporate responsibility to respect human rights. A richer approach might have recast the third
pillar access to remedies away from the
stakeholders at the center of the first two pillars—states, business
enterprises, non-governmental organizations, public international
organizations—and toward the critical object of this enterprise—individuals
suffering adverse human rights impacts. The remedial provisions assume a more
autonomous role by centering its provisions on the obligations and privileges
of stakeholders who belong to that class of individuals or groups affects by
state or corporate activity with human rights impacts. Thus turned around, access to remedy becomes
a more useful vehicle for the elaboration of the obligations of actors to avoid
and remediate harm. That obligation, of
course in accordance with the structure of the Guiding Principles, be limited
to law (legislation and dispute resolution remediation) for states, and
governance norm frameworks (social norms and contract policies, including the
policies at the heart of human rights due diligence) for corporate actors. Within that framework, international organizations
and other collectives organized to fashion standards and remediation might also
assume a greater place within the constellation of remedial alternatives
available to individuals. One could try
to interpret the current framework in that direction, but it is more likely
that a consequentialist structure will be used.
The result is the loss of a mechanics, inherent in the development of
the “Protect, Respect and Remedy” framework that might have fleshed out the
relationship, within these complex and overlapping governance structures, of
the rights bearers to those whose actions may adversely affect their
interests.
7. Inter-systemic Issues. The great
challenge of polycentric structuring is the approaches chosen for the ordering
of the relationship between coordinating systems, that is, the challenge of the
effectiveness of their structural coupling.[44]
The issues of interactions among state and corporate governance systems, along
with that of international public and private organizations that supplement and
compete with both, presents an important unresolved issue that parallels that
of the future of legitimate interpretation of the Guiding Principles
themselves. On the one hand, this
process can be understood as organic, subject to the sum of the combination of
the logic of the character of each of the actors. On the other, the strong instrumentalist
character of the Guiding Principles opens a great temptation to coordination
and management of these relationships, and likely to some or another greater
end, that have some substantial limitations.[45]
Second, autonomy of the
corporate responsibility is also built into the scope of application rules of
DP Principle 12 (GP Principles 12-15).
The responsibility applies “across
a business enterprise’s activities and through its relationships with third
parties associated with those activities”[46]
The validity of this scope is problematic, at best, under the rules of the
domestic legal orders of most states. It
disregards the complex and deeply embedded legal protections accorded to
entities separately constituted as legal persons. It would ignore principles of asset segregate
built into the legal regimes of corporate limited liability. It ignores rules for piercing the corporate
veil. It also converts contract law into
governance relationships, especially to the extent it a seeks to impose
obligations to control behavior on the entity in the superior position within
supply or value chains. Activity rather
than legal relationships form the touchstone of the scope of the responsibility
to protect.[47]
None of this is necessarily bad; but all of it suggests a basis in legitimacy
well outside the construct of the law system rules of domestic legal orders.[48] The essence of corporate personality and the
character of its relationships with others is grounded in substantially
different standards outside the law state system than within it. GP Principle 12 is built on the recognition
of that distinction.
Third, autonomy is also built
into the construction of GP Principle 14’s application to “all enterprises
regardless of their size, sector, operational context, ownership and structure.”[49] This
portion of the standard effectively ignores the rules of legal personality on
which the law of corporations in virtually every state is based. The standard collapses corporate personality
into single enterprises the legal consequences of the actions of any portions
of which triggers the responsibility to respect within the entire
enterprise. This is impossible under the
domestic law of most states, which for example, would impose strict fiduciary
duty rules on the boards of distinct corporations making up an enterprise. The GP suggests that while the obligations
corporations may be grounded on the basis of particular standards according to
the laws of the states in which they are domiciled or operate, the
responsibility to respect human rights is not limited by those legal rules.
Fourth, the basis of the
responsibility to respect appears to be functional rather than formal. It is to some extent grounded in principles
of power relationships. If a corporation
has power over another in the context of their relationship, that corporation
has a responsibility to respect human rights within the context of that power.[50] Importantly, protection from legal liability
does not follow from compliance with the autonomous obligations derived from
the corporate responsibility to respect.[51]
Thus, compliance with corporate responsibility rules does not insulate a
corporation form liability under the law based rules of the states in which it
is domiciled or operates.
Fifth, the functional element
of the responsibility to respect, and its autonomy from law, is emphasized in
the description of the governance universe that makes up the substantive
element of the responsibility to respect.
“Depending on circumstances,
companies may need to consider additional standards.”[52] These are sourced in international rather
than the domestic law of any state, with specific reference to international
humanitarian law and the universe of U.N. instruments specific to vulnerable
and/or marginalized groups, such as indigenous peoples, women, ethnic and
religious minorities, and children.[53]
Lastly, the scope rules of
the responsibility to respect human rights includes a strong caution against a
conventional approach to its effectuation, grounded in notions of risk
assessment common to financial reporting.
The Commentary makes clear that a risk assessment approach should not be
undertaken, especially one in which the costs of compliance are balanced against
the benefits accruing to a failure to respect human rights. Likewise companies may not balance the
benefits of respecting human rights in one instance against their failures to
respect human rights in others.[54] With these caveats, though, some room for
incorporation within the risk management functions of corporate operations is
permitted.[55]
But this systemic autonomy bumps
up against reality as well. One in
particular is worth mention here; it is emblematic of the sort of tension that
might threaten this Guiding Principles construct—the actions required of an
enterprise where the laws of a domestic legal order conflicts with the social
or international norms to which the corporation might also be bound. The
Guiding Principles do not focus on this issue directly, but the thrust of the
approach is clear—the rules of the domestic legal order preempt competing
norms.[56] But the Principles in this case tend to
inhibit rather than encourage bridging action in an effort to bend to the
hierarchy of law that frames the Principles.
For example, it might have
been possible to suggest a more instrumental balancing when corporations are
faced with conflicting requirements based on the sort of decision balancing
procedures and proportionality principles already well embedded in the
Principles.[57] That
instrumental balancing could proceed through four decision steps: (1)
exploration of the possibility of reconciling the conflict between standards
through interpretation;[58]
(2) if no reconciliation possible, negotiation of an exception or solution with
the State;[59]
(3) if mediation or informal discussion with State officials is unsuccessful,
then challenge the law;[60]
and (4) where challenge is unsuccessful consideration of the continued
feasibility of operating in the offending jurisdiction, assuming that the
company is now forced to choose between national and international standards.[61]
Only
when lawful challenge proves unsuccessful does a company actually face the
issue suggested by the problem--reconciling inconsistent national and
international obligations to respect human rights. In that case, the company
must make a decision based on the greater good in terms of human rights.[62]
The example of Google's well publicized initial determination to engage in
business in China in the face of national censorship requirements provides a
good illustration of the nature of the decision. In that case, Google decided
that there was more human rights benefits to providing some greater amount of
information to Chinese customers than to abandon China altogether.[63]
It is important to remember that decisions made in this context are
dynamic. They require constant review as circumstances change. Where the human
rights benefits diminish in the face of continued inconsistency in legal requirements,
and then the company must reevaluate its business decision in order to meet its
"respect" requirements under the three pillar mandate. Again, Google
provides a good illustration. The Company publicly sought to reevaluate
its agreement to comply with Chinese censorship rules in the aftermath of
cyber attacks on its operations.[64]
All of these steps could be more effective if taken in collaboration with peer companies, nongovernmental allies, and where applicable the home state.[65] This is especially useful where these collectives can develop models of decision and analysis that are context specific--the example for labor issues, or for issues peculiar to a particular industrial sector. It might also provide a useful area to stimulate collaboration between industry and civil society groups. It is in this context that the General Principles missed an opportunity to mirror the multilateral governance provisions of the state duty to the corporate responsibility, including the incorporation of the General Principles themselves in the work of multilateral corporate groups.[66] That absence illustrates both the promise and the limits of the General Principles in its initial iteration.
Innovation is never
perfect—either in conception or implementation.
Reality always serves as the ultimate limiting principle for both theory
and practice. All innovative movements
have confronted this reality. Those that
have remained unbending have failed; those that have sought to preserve what
they could to advance their project in the face of the constraints that reality
imposes tend to survive, and sometimes flourish. The SRSG’s voyage of principled pragmatism
has served the “Protect, Respect and Remedy” framework well; its insights have
produced the shortfalls examined at length in the body of this work, but also
marked the extraordinary success of the project itself. This is no small matter—despite the pessimism
of all stakeholders—states, corporations, non-governmental and public international—the
SRSG was able to craft a coherent system of governance and obtain official
endorsement of states acting through an international organization not known
for its unity of vision or purpose. That alone will be the object of study by
political scientists, institutional theorists and sociologists for some time to
come. The object of this article,
though, was the framework itself.
Articled as a set of dense principles, and whatever its shortcomings, it
has opened a number of significant pathways to development of law and
governance frameworks. It accepts that
there are formal systems of governance beyond those of the state. It begins to make a pragmatic case for the
interlacing of international law and domestic legal orders, it recognizes the
governance aspects of social norm systems and seeks a method of institutionalizing
that role, it broadens the scope of remediation in a systematic way and attempts
to harmonize the principles that serve as markets of legitimacy and accountability
for each. The Guiding Principles manage
this within a overall framework that still grounds its operation in and through
states and which continues to treat corporations and other actors as dependent
on and subject to an exclusive (at least in the aggregate) control of states
through law in ways that even states now find troublesome.[67] It is
likely to play a significant role in the development of governance frameworks
in this area for some time to time.
(From Srah Altschuller, Human Rights Due Diligence and the Corporate Lawyer, Corporate Social Responsibility and the Law, Oct. 24, 2010))
[1] 2011 Report, supra, Para. 2.
[2] John Knox. The Human Rights Council
Endorses “Guiding Principles” for Corporations, 15(21) Insights: American Society of International Law, Aug. 1,
2011. Available http://www.asil.org/pdfs/insights/insight110801.pdf.
[3] See, e.g., Bruno Simma and Philip
Alston, The Sources of Human Rights Law:
Custom, Jus Cogens, and General Principles, 12 Australian Yearbook of International Law 82-108 (1992).
[4] See Inter-American Court of Human
Rights, Advisory Opinion OC-18/03 (Sept. 17, 2003) Juridical Condition and
Rights of Undocumented Migrants (United Mexican States) (http://www.corteidh.or.cr/opiniones.cfm?idOpinion=24).
[5] This principle of non-self-executing
treaties has been particularly well developed within the recent jurisprudence
of the United States. See, e.g.,
Medellín v. Texas, 552 U.S. 491 (2008).
[6] See e.g., Edward T. Swaine, Reserving, 31 Yale J. Int’l L. 307 (2006); Laurence R. Helfer, Not Fully Committed? Reservations, Risk, and
Treaty Design, 31 Yale J. Int’l L.
367 (2006).
[7] See Robert Y. Jennings, The International Court of Justice After
Fifty Years, 89(3) American Journal
of International Law 493 (1995).
[8] See, e.g., Emilia Justyna Powell,
and Sara McLaughlin Mitchell, The International Court of Justice and the
World's Three Legal Systems, 69(2) Journal
of Politics 397-415 (2007).
[9] That was a significant concession to
states from the original draft of the Guiding Principles in which the scope of
the human rights instruments was included in a definitions section.
[10] Opening Statement to United Nations
Human Rights Council, Professor John G. Ruggie, Special Representative of the
Secretary-General for Business and Human Rights, Geneva, 25 September 2006.
[11] GP Principle 2, and discussion supra
at ----.
[12] Westel
W. Willoughby, The Fundamental Concepts Of Public Law 309 (New York: MacMillan,
1924).
[13] The reverse is unlikely—for example
the extraterritorial control of corporate activity from small and less well off
states into larger and richer states.
The reasons are obvious. More
interesting is the possibility of clashes in business culture and values
between values exporting states whose governance system values are not
compatible. The battle for values dominance
under the model of GP Principle 2 would occur not in the halls of international
institutions nor in the territories of the home states but would be fought in
the territories of host states where both extraterritorial rivals would be
competing for business. The best example of that is the contests, already
occurring, between Chinese and European firms in Africa. See, e.g., Jon W. Walker, China, U.S. And Africa:
Competition Or Cooperation?, U.S. Army War College Strategy Research Project,
March 15, 2008. Available http://www.dtic.mil/cgi-bin/GetTRDoc?Location=U2&doc=GetTRDoc.pdf&AD=ADA481365.
For an example of the reporting in the popular press, see, e.g., Antoaneta Becker, China-EU Rivalry in Africa Sharpens,
Inter-Press Service News Agency, June 15, 2010.
Available http://ipsnews.net/news.asp?idnews=51831.
[14] See, e.g., Larry Catá Backer, Part I: Developing a Coherent Transnational
Jurisprudence of Ethical Investing: The Norwegian Sovereign Wealth Fund Ethics
Council Model, Law at the End of the Day, Feb. 1, 2011.
[15] “The result is effectively a
handbook for the implementation of a comprehensive system for the management of
business and human rights, with clear guidance for states and corporations.” Peter Davis, Opinion: John Ruggie:
A Common Focus for Human Rights, Ethical Corporation, Available, http://www.ethicalcorp.com/content.asp?contentid=7253.
[16] Cf., Renaud
Dehousse, The European Court of Justice:
The Politics of Judicial Integration (New York: St. Martin’s
Press, 1999).
[17] Cf. Kawi
Hang Ng, The Common Law in Two Voices:
Language, Law and the Postcolonial Dilemma in Hong Kong
(Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2009) (on the complex relationship between juridical formalism, language and
legal norms in Hong Kong)).
[18] On the formalization issues of
multinational policy, see, e.g., Anant R. Nergandhi, External and Internal Functioning of American, German and Japanese
Multinaitonal Corporations: Decisionmaking
and Policy Issues, in Governments
and Multinationals: The Policy of
Control Versus Autonomy 21 (Walter H. Goldberg and Ananti R. Negandhi,
eds., Cambridge: Oelgeschlager, Gunn & Hain, publishers, 1983).
[19] See, e.g., Larry Catá Backer, Multinational Corporations as Objects and
Sources of Transnational Regulation, 14 ILSA Journal Of International & Comparative Law 499 (2008).
[20] See, e.g., Larry Catá Backer, Economic Globalization and the Rise of
Efficient Systems of Global Private Law Making:
Wal-Mart as Global Legislator,
39(4) University Of Connecticut Law Review 1739 (2007).
[21] See, e.g., Howard Schweber, The Language of Liberal Constitutionalism
81-134 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007).
[22] See, e.g., Larry Catá Backer, From Moral Obligation to International Law:
Disclosure Systems, Markets and the Regulation of Multinational Corporations,
39 Georgetown Journal Of International
Law 591 (2008).
[23] The Guiding Principles recognize
that this evolution will occur within an
imperative that looks “for ways of coordinating public and private rulemaking
in such a way as to preserve both social autonomy and the public interest.” Harm Schepel, The Constitution of Private
Governance: Product Standards in the
Regulation of Integrating Markets 32 (Oxford: Hart, 2005).
[24] The SRSG recognized the difficulties
of an all purpose approach, as well as the allure of its simplicity for
business and sought to road test the device .
See Introduction to the Guiding Principles 2011, supra. Para. 11. More field testing will likely produce
additional sophistication in the development and deployment of the device.
[25] Larry Catá Backer, The Surveillance State: Monitoring
as Regulation, Information as Power, Law at the End of the Day, Dec.
21, 2007. See, Larry Catá Backer, Global Panopticism: States, Corporations and
the Governance Effects of Monitoring Regimes, 15 Indiana Journal of Global
Legal Studies, 15(1) Indiana Journal
Of Global Legal Studies 101 (2008). “It can be used to decide what sorts
of facts constitute information, to determine what sorts of information ought
to be privileged and which do not matter, to gather that information, to empower
people or entities to gather information, to act on the information gathered.”
Id.
[26] “In its domestic form it can be used
to assign authority over certain types of information to private enterprises
and then hold those enterprises to account on the basis of the information
gathered.” Id.
[27] “In its transnational form it can be
used to construct a set of privileged information that can be gathered and
distributed voluntarily by private entities on the basis of systems created and
maintained by international public or private organizations as an alternative
to formal regulation and to provide a means of harmonizing behavior without
law.” Id.
[28] Larry Catá Backer, The Surveillace State: Monitoring as
Regulation, Information as PowerLaw at the End of the Day, Dec. 21, 2007. See, Larry Catá
Backer, Global Panopticism: States, Corporations and the
Governance Effects of Monitoring Regimes, 15 Indiana Journal of Global Legal
Studies -- (forthcoming 2007).
[29] For a discussion of prioritization,
see, Larry Catá Backer, Business and Human Rights Part XVII--Implementation:
Prioritizing, Law at the End of the Day, Feb. 18, 2010.
[30] United Nations Special
Representative of the Secretary-General on Business & Human Rights, Issues:
Gender.
[31] See, Larry Catá Backer, Business and Human Rights Part
XVI--Implementation: When International and National Norms Conflict, Law at the End of the Day, Feb. 17,
2010.
[32] The Sullivan Principles. Available http://muweb.marshall.edu/revleonsullivan/principled/principles.htm. .
[33] GP Principle 7 discussed supra.
[34] For the classic explanation, see, Westel W. Willoughby, The Fundamental Concepts Of
Public Law 307-309 (New York: MacMillan,
1924) (“Such States may be said to occupy in the international system much the
same position as persons subject to the disabilities of infancy or alienage
occupy in municipal law, but their exact position is hard to define.” Id., at
308).
[35] The corporation is directed merely
to beware the dangers of complicity on conflict zones. GP Principle 23.
[36] Indeed, the current framework
supports the charge made by some states that the present system of
globalization is meant to strengthen the hand of strong states to deal with
weaker ones and reimpose the old system of hierarchy in the relations among
states as a formal matter, or that the system itself is meant to favor the
designs of global hegemons. See, e.g..,
Larry Catá Backer, Economic Globalization
Ascendant: Four Perspectives on the
Emerging Ideology of the State in the New Global Order, 17(1) Berkeley La
Raza Law Journal 141, 154-162 (2006).
[37] GP Principle 7, discussed supra.
[38] See, GP Principle 14, discussed
above.
[39] Fort he relevant discussion of the
European approach in the context of the “golden share” cases, see, Larry Catá
Backer, The Private Law of Public
Law: Public Authorities As Shareholders,
Golden Shares, Sovereign Wealth Funds, And The Public Law Element In Private
Choice of Law, 82(5) Tulane Law
Review 1801 (2008).
[40] See 2009 Report, supra and 2010
Report, supra. and discussion supra.
[41] See, e.g., Louis Henkin, A New Birth of Constitutionalism: Genetic Influences and Genetic Defects, in
Constitutionalism, Identity, Difference
and Legitimacy: Theoretical Perspectives 39, 40-42 (Michel Rosenfeld,
ed., Duke University Press, 1994).
[42] See GP Principles 28-30.
[43] See, e.g., Amnesty International,
Comments in Response to the Special Representative of the UN Secretary General
on Transnational Corporations and Other Business Enterprises’ Guiding
Principles—Proposed Outline (October 2010) IOR 50/001/2010, at 18-21 (“The
Guiding Principles must be clear that there will be some corporate human rights
impacts that must involve the State ensuring accountability and remedy.” Id.,
at 21).
[44] See, e.g., Niklas Luhmann, Operational Closure and Structural
Coupling: The Differentiation of the
Legal System, 13 Cardozo L. Rev.
1419 (1991-92).
[45] This is what Bob Jessop has
described in a related context as the tension between what is sometimes derided
as market anarchy and organizational
hierarchy. See, Bob Jessop, The
Governance of Complexity and the Complexity or Governance: Preliminary Remarks on Some Problems and
Limits of Economic Guidance, in Beyond
Market and Hierarchy: Interactive
Governance and Social Complexity 95 (Cheltenham, UK;: Edward Elgar,
2010) (“inter-systemic concertation must be mediated through subjects who can
engage in ex ante self-regulatory strategic coordination, monitor the effects
of that coordination on goal attainment and modify their strategies as
appropriate. On the other hand, such bodies
can never fully represent the operational logic. . .of whole subsystems.” Id.,
at 113).
[46] GP Principle 12.
[47] The Commentary emphasizes that “The scope of the corporate responsibility to
respect human rights extends across a business enterprise’s own activities and
through its relationships with other parties, such as business partners,
entities in its value chain, other non- State actors and State agents.
Particular country and local contexts may affect the human rights risks of an
enterprise’s activities and relationships.” GP Principle 12
Commentary.
[48] See, e.g., Larry CatILSA J. Int’l & Comp. L. 499
(2008).. a Backer, Multinational
Corporations as Objects and Sources of Transnational Regulation, 14
[49] GP Principle 14.
[50] The idea is grounded in the concept of leverage. GP
Principle 19(b)(ii). See discussion, supra, at ---. In the Draft Guiding Principles Commentary
these ideas were grounded in notions of influence. It explains:
“‘Influence’, where defined as
‘leverage’, is not a basis for attributing responsibility to business
enterprises for adverse human rights impacts. Rather, a business enterprise’s
leverage over third parties becomes relevant in identifying what it can
reasonably do to prevent and mitigate its potential human rights impacts or
help remediate any actual impacts for which it is responsible.” DP Principle 12 Commentary.
[51] The Commentary makes that point
explicitly:
Conducting
appropriate human rights due diligence should help business enterprises address
the risk of legal claims against them by showing that they took every
reasonable step to avoid involvement with an alleged human rights abuse. However,
business enterprises conducting such due diligence should not assume that, by
itself, this will automatically and fully absolve them from liability for
causing or contributing to human rights abuses.
GP Principle 17 Commentary.
[52] GP Principle 12 Commentary.
[53] Id.
[54] “The responsibility to respect does not preclude business enterprises
from undertaking additional commitments or activities to support and promote
human rights. But such desirable activities cannot offset an enterprise’s
failure to respect human rights throughout its operations and relationships.”
GP Principle 12 Commentary.
[55] “Human rights due diligence can be included within broader enterprise
risk management systems provided that it goes beyond simply identifying and
managing material risks to the company itself to include the risks a company’s
activities and associated relationships may pose to the rights of affected
individuals and communities.” GP Principle 15 Commentary.
[56] GP Principle 23 speaks to seeking
ways to honor principles of human rights when faced with conflicting
requirements. GP Principle 23(b) and
discussion, supra. This is consistent
with the overall framework of the Guiding Principles. See GP Principles 1 and 3.
[58]
The exercise of reconciling standards can involve the efforts of a number of
departments in the corporation. Lawyers might be tasked to determine whether
there are reasonable ways to avoid conflict, or whether reasonable alternative
interpretations of national or international law is feasible; industry
standards or local practice might be reviewed; officials might reach out to
international bodies or local civil society elements for interpretation.
Additionally, the company might review its planned actions in light of its
objectives. Many times it may be possible to find alternative means to the same
objective that avoids conflict. These processes are usually informal but can
also lead to a decision to invoke formal processes for definitive
interpretation (and thus lead to stage two).
[59] In this stage, there is an
assumption that reconciliation is impossible and alternative means of avoiding
conflict are not feasible. Now both formal and informal contacts must be made
with the appropriate State officials to seek top mediate the conflict. This may
involve a number of alternative approaches, from negotiating an agreement with
the State (with the object of reaching an agreement that avoids violation of
human rights norms), to seeking protection under bilateral investment treaties
that incorporate international standards, to seeking legislative change in an
appropriate manner.
[60] It is possible that discussions with
State officials may not produce agreement that satisfies the requirements of
international standards. In that event, the company must determine whether it
ought to challenge the inconsistent national legislation. Challenge may take
one of two forms in most cases. Usually this course suggests a legal challenge
to inconsistent state law. Sometimes it may suggest political challenge. In the
latter event, it may be important to solicit the help and counsel of local
civil society elements. Special sensitivity ought to be exercised when engaging
in challenge in countries with weak government or in conflict zones.
[61] It is possible that discussions with
State officials may not produce agreement that satisfies the requirements of
international standards. In that event, the company must determine whether it
ought to challenge the inconsistent national legislation. Challenge may take
one of two forms in most cases. Usually this course suggests a legal challenge
to inconsistent state law. Sometimes it may suggest political challenge. In the
latter event, it may be important to solicit the help and counsel of local civil
society elements. Special sensitivity ought to be exercised when engaging in
challenge in countries with weak government or in conflict zones.
[62] The idea is well known in the
business literature. Seem,, e.g., Thomas N. Gladwin and Ingo Walter, Multinationals
Under Fire: Lessons in the Management of
Conflict 206-212 (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1981) (withdrawal
form apartheid South Africa). These
decisions are grounded in the application of social norm ideals. These
are made evident through social mobilization and action by consumers,
shareholders and non governmental organizations that may affect public opinion
and economic decision-making affecting corporate profitability. See, e g., Susanne
Soederberg, Corporate Power and Ownership in Contemporary Capitalism: The Politics of Resistance and Domination
138-159 (London: Routledge, 2009)
(speaking to what she labels the marketization of social justice illustrated by
the case of the Sudan divestment campaign).
[65] Compare G.P. Principle 10 and
discussion, supra.
[66] The closest provision, GP Principle
30, sets a substantive constraint on multi-stakeholder and other collaboration
initiatives. It assumes such efforts
without encouraging them or considering them important instrumental elements in
furthering the framework, nor does it provide a structure for collaborations
between them and business in the construction and implementation of their human
rights due diligence programs. It does recognize these possibilities, but
gently. It does suggest the similarity
in issues of implementation but does not focus on the connection with other
related systems.
[67]
For a discussion, see, Larry Catá Backer, Private
Governance, Soft Law, and the Construction of Polycentric Networks for the
Regulation of Transnational Corporations, 17(1) Indiana Journal Of Global Legal Studies -- (forthcoming
2011).
No comments:
Post a Comment