Pix Credit here |
In Basu v. Germany (215/19; Judgment 18.10.2022 [Section III Information Note published; Text of 3rd Section here and here], the European Court of Human Rights (ECHR) considered the applicability of Article 14 (prohibition of discrimination) taken in conjunction with Article 8 (right to respect for private and family life) to the following set of facts:
In July 2012 two police officers carried out an identity check on the applicant, a German national of Indian origin, and his daughter, on a train which had just passed the border from the Czech Republic to Germany. The applicant asked the police officers why he was checked, and they said it was a random check. One of them later added that cigarettes were frequently smuggled on that train, but confirmed that there had not been any specific suspicion in respect of the applicant in this regard. The administrative courts declined to examine the merits of the applicant’s complaint about having been treated in a discriminatory manner by the identity check. (Basu v. Germany)
The ECHR concluded that (A) "the identity check by the police under these special circumstances had had sufficiently serious consequences for his right to respect for his private life. The identity check in question therefore felt within the ambit of Article 8;" and (B) "the State authorities had failed to comply with their duty to take all reasonable measures to ascertain through an independent body whether or not a discriminatory attitude had played a role in the identity check, and thus had failed to carry out an effective investigation in this regard." (Ibid.).
The folks at the Völkerrechtsblog have now confronted this issue in a very interesting online symposium: Racial Profiling in Germany. "In this symposium, scholars reflect on the European Court of Human
Rights’ recent Basu v. Germany decision. They situate the decision
within recent conversations surrounding race and racism in Germany and
in international human rights discourse more broadly." (Racial Profiling in Germany Symposium). The Symposium Introduction provides a nice description:
In Basu v. Germany, an international body reminded Germany once again of its less-than-perfect human rights record regarding racial discrimination. In this case, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) ruled that Germany had violated the right to privacy according to Article 8 of the European of Human Rights (ECHR) in conjunction with the right to non-discrimination (Article 14 ECHR) by failing to provide a proper and independent investigation into allegations of racial profiling. This symposium takes the decision as a starting point to reflect on the practice of racial profiling in Germany and, more generally, on the place of race and racism in Germany and in international human rights discourse. (Racial Profiling in Germany )
The excellent symposium essays seek to translate the practices at issue in Basu v. Germany into the language of race and racism (and this appears to be an easy case in that respect given the sensibilities of the times). At the same time, the essays provide a doorway through which it might also be worth looking at the larger issues lurking in the background.
I will be posting the Symposium contributions here and will also contribute some brief reflections and engagement with each of the excellent and thought provoking contributions. For this Part 3 we consider Elisabeth Kaneza's excellent essay, "Human Rights Standards for Accountability and Effective Remedies." Kaneza focuses on a legal and normative construction of profiling--in the context of information that is or can have discriminatory effects. The essay is particularly useful for helping to unpack the issue of definition (of profiling) and with it the normative baseline from which such definitional possibilities may be identified. The three standards for triggering remediation of prohibited discrimination--(1) "mainly prompted"; (2) "objective and reasonable justification"; (3) "to any degree"--are usefully compared to the standard that appears to be emerging from Basu v. Germany and its two part "severity" standard. Kaneza makes a case for the "to any degree" standard; my observations suggest consequences for data driven descriptive and predictive analytics.Other Essays and Reflections produced for this online symposium may be accessed here:
Part I Introduction
Part 2 Observations on the Case Information Note
Part 3: Observations on Elisabeth Kaneza, "Human Rights Standards for Accountability and Effective Remedies.Part 4: Observations on Anna Hankings-Evans, "Race and Empire in International Law"
Part 5: Observations on Lisa Washington, "Racist Police Practices"
Observations on Elisabeth Kaneza, "Human Rights Standards for Accountability and Effective Remedies."
1. Kaneza starts with the observation that Germans thought that discriminatory profiling was a problem in foreign states. Yet, certainly after 2012, German courts have been sensitive to the issue (here). The issue for Germany since has been one based on a "mainly prompted" standard. Of course the door was then opened to a more complicated analytics. Certainly, though relying principally on racial or ethnic (one presumes as well religious) identity markers (however constituted as data--a point that remains to be fully developed) is forbidden, factoring those characteristics in other ways may not be. The line drawing of statutory (and constitutional) application, then, results in challenges for descriptive and predictive analytics, the sophistication and effective targeting of the application of which may well require the inclusion of data that, when given prominence (or that drives analytics) is forbidden as discriminatory (in intent or effect).
2. Kaneza suggests, correctly, that the gateway issue for this emerging jurisprudence (whether within the German judicial apparatus, or from out of the construction of overarching international normative constraints) starts with definition. The semiotics of discrimination generally, and of profiling in particular, suggests that data analytics can be shaped by the conscious investment of data objects with meaning that in turn aligns the understanding of a term with its specific ideological foundation (in this case the principle of anti-discrimination). Kaneza notes the absence of consensus definition but points to a useful starting point for moving toward a more universal consensus on the meaning of the term. To that end Kaneza turns to the management of the meaning of the term "profiling" by international norm/narrative producing organs. Specific reference is made to the well known European Commission against Racism and Intolerance (ECRI) 2007 definition of racial profiling in its general policy recommendation No. 11 and its "objective and reasonable justification" standard. Also noted was the 2020 definition put forward by the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (CERD) in its general recommendation No. 36 (drawing the Durban Programme of Action (2001) ¶72's "to any degree" standard" CERD GR No. 36 ¶7). The CERD standard, however, applies the "to any degree" standard only to instances of profiling, which is itself defined to exclude such data when it is "motivated by objective criteria or reasonable justification" even when "based on grounds of race, colour, descent, national or ethnic origin or their intersection with other relevant grounds" (CERD GR ¶ 13).
3. Of the three, the "to any degree" standard is the most restrictive in terms of the use of race based data or factors in exercising police discretion or even in analyzing compliance with law. The "objective and reasonable justification" standard permits the inclusion of race based data in analytics and race based contextual factoring in exercising of discretionary police action but only in furtherance of a legitimate aim or where it can be established that there exists a proportional relationship between means and (legitimate) aims. The "mainly prompted" standard appears to be the most forgiving. Under this standard evidence that race or ethnicity based factors were incidental rather than the primary predicate for the police action appears to be enough.
4. The standards adopted in Basu v. Germany falls somewhere in the middle (see discussion here and noting that the majority did not engage very critically with the standards identified by Kaneza or raised to a more limited extent in the partial dissent of Judge Pavli; Partial Dissent ¶¶9-12). The Basu court rejected an interpretation of the European Human Rights Charter that would move that discrimination jurisprudence at least respecting profiling closer to the "to any degree" standard. The adopted severity threshold principle makes that clear. With respect to the tests for the showing of severity, the circumstantial evidence standard requires a showing that "the person
concerned had submitted that he or she (or persons having the same
characteristics) had been the only person(s) subjected to a check" AND
that "no other grounds for the check had been apparent." The direct
evidentiary standard is met "where any explanations of the officers
carrying out the check disclosed specific physical or ethnic motives for
the check." (Basu v. Germany, (a)). This later standard might be closer to the "mainly prompted" standard (where the race profiling disclosure suggested discriminatory intent), though it could be read strictly (to suggest that any mention of race or ethnicity is enough to trigger the standard, and thus closer to the "to any degree" standard).
5. Kaneza's sympathies gravitate toward the "to any degree" standard. And Kaneza makes powerful arguments to advance that approach. These focus n historical disadvantage and socio-economic marginalization. Together the principle applied is one of vulnerability serving to tip the balance of interpretation from one that can embed race and ethnicity data within analytics and thereafter operations, to one that ought not. That tipping is contextual--profiling in police work, but perhaps not in the development of metrics and discretionary choices furthering social justice projects. And there is little to say about the use of the data as a necessary element of meeting the severity standards and thereafter in guiding independent state investigation upon the proffering of a credible demand.
6. The argument is said to have special application in the German context. It is for that reason (eg, the shadow of National Socialism in the development of the German constitutional order for example) that Kaneza suggests a necessary dissatisfaction with the current state of German jurisprudence around profiling. Moreover Kaneza's reading of that jurisprudence as inconsistent also suggests a space for further development., in this case away from the "mainly prompted" standard.
7. Lastly, Kaneza underscores the ECHR's emphasis on aspects of procedural fairness in the application of the state's positive obligation to investigate discrimination complaints that meet the "severity" threshold. Here again CERD's General Recommendation No. 36 (¶ 39) is suggested as a basis for the construction of such remedial mechanisms. In this case, it might be that the construction of institutions and mechanisms for independent investigation might necessarily be predicated on the fundamental approach embraced. Nonetheless, the issue of data, data analytics, and its relationship to standards and operational practices remains to be confronted.
* * * * * *
Human Rights Standards for Accountability and Effective Remedies
Racial Profiling in Germany
13.12.2022
Elisabeth Kaneza is community outreach officer at the German Center for Integration and Migration Studies (DeZIM-Institut) as well as founder and head of the Kaneza Foundation. She recently defended her doctoral thesis on the rights of Black people in Germany at the University of Potsdam.
No comments:
Post a Comment