(Pix (c) Larry Catá Backer 2014)
Since 2010, I have been posting on the development of a new course I
have been developing for our first year law school students, "Elements
of Law." The course originally had a quite modest objective--to
introduce law students to legal research and reasoning through case law,
statutory interpretation, and legal history, processes, and
institutions. I chose to broaden its objectives within these specific
parameters and development a framing and concepts course that would
provide a deep foundation to law students on the legal system they were
undertaking to study.
This and the posts that follow produces some of the materials I will be presenting to the class. I offer these materials in hopes that they may prove of use and that you might share comments, perspectives and suggestions as I develop those materials on this site. Thanks.
This post includes a draft of the second Chapter of Part II-- Hierarchies of Law and Governance; Sources and Uses, Chapter 10 (Hierarchies of Law within the Domestic Legal Order and Between National and International Law Reflecting Governmental Order).
--Elements of Law 3.0: On the Relevance of a First Year Law Course Designed to Frame the Law School Curriculum).Grounded in the principles of the sociology of law, the course has morphed into an effort to introduce students to law as a self-referencing system with its own particular structures, premises, constraints and language, with its own logic and taboos and its own means of understanding the world. That systemicity (cf. Peter Checkland, Systems Thinking, Systems Practice, Chichester : John Wiley and Sons Ltd, 1999) is then a critical element in the way in which the legal system (in this case of the United States) interacts with the world, both as a legal and as a socio-economic-political actor. The course has also expanded from its original narrow and technical focus, to a broader focus on principles and the use of language and logic to build and operate a system of law. That broadening has made it possible to offer the course not just to first year law students, but also to graduate students in the social sciences and in international affairs, as a grounding in the legal systems that are important in their respective fields.
--Developing a New Course--"Elements of Law"
--"Elements of Law" Course 2.0: A Framework Course for the U.S. Law Curriculum,
This and the posts that follow produces some of the materials I will be presenting to the class. I offer these materials in hopes that they may prove of use and that you might share comments, perspectives and suggestions as I develop those materials on this site. Thanks.
This post includes a draft of the second Chapter of Part II-- Hierarchies of Law and Governance; Sources and Uses, Chapter 10 (Hierarchies of Law within the Domestic Legal Order and Between National and International Law Reflecting Governmental Order).
Chapter
10
Hierarchies
of Law within the Domestic Legal Order and Between National and International
Law Reflecting Governmental Order
I.
Introduction
We have
been considering the way in which the United States has developed a set of
principles to systematically organize the relationship between law and the
apparatus of state (its government). We
have seen how that initial decision produced a compromise of sorts between two
competing ways of conceptualizing the state-law nexus. The first understood law as inevitably tied
to and produced only by the apparatus of state as a representative avatar for
the people as sovereigns. The second
represented an evolution of the old medieval understanding of law as autonomous
of the state (and its government). That autonomy, of course, was not
absolute—the legislature could project power into law by enacting
statutes. Yet early on, there was also a
sense that higher order values might not be interfered with by either the
legislature (Parliament) or the executive (the Crown), though together (as
Crown in Parliament) they might be vested with the authority to act as or for
the sovereign people. We have come to understand how these premises shaped the
development of a two tier structure of law with different relationships to the
state. Higher Order or Constitutional
law remains somewhat autonomous of the state and can only be amended at great
effort. Other forms of law may be more
easily made. Yet even there the notion
of separation remains lurking.
We have
also begun to understand how this grounding notion of law-state structure
produced a need for ordering among law.
If, as we have come to understand it, the law system fo the United
States includes several sub-systemic strands that overlap, and if we also have
come to understand the governmental system of the United States as layered
among local, state and federal authority, then some structural guidance is necessary
in order to make the U.S. legal system coherent rather than chaotic. It is to that point that we considered the
way in which hierarchies of law have been established both within states and
between states and the general government in Washington D.C.
With this
chapter we broaden our gaze just a little more. This section introduces the
student to the issues of legal hierarchy in the context of the state system on
which the contemporary global legal and political order is founded. The student
will examine the relationship between domestic and international law in
relation to the obligation of the state and the obligations of individuals. That has tended to be a complex business sin
the United States, the outer limits of which remain quite lively areas of
debate. The problem at the end of the
chapter is meant to help students apply some of the premises underlying U.S.
approaches to the incorporation of international law and principles within its
domestic jurisprudence and the way in which that international legalization can
actually penetrate into the U.S. legal system.
II. Chapter Readings
· Larry
Catá Backer, Inter-Systemic Harmonization and Its Challenges for the
Legal-State,[1]
in FICHL Publication Series No. 11 (2011): The Law of the Future and the Future
of the Law 427-437 (Editors: Sam Muller, Stavros Zouridis, MorlyFrishman and
Laura Kistemaker; TorkelOpsahl Academic EPublisher, Oslo, 2011)
· Medellín
v. Texas[2],128
S.Ct. 1346 (2008) (READ MAJORITY OPINION and skim concurring and dissenting opinions
· PruneYard
Shopping Ctr. V. Robins,[3] 447 U.
S. 74 (1980). Read pp 74-81
__________
Inter-Systemic Harmonization And Its Challenges For The
Legal-State
Larry Catá
Backer
HiiL Law of the
Future Series, The Law of the Future and
the Future of Law
(Sam Muller,
Stavros Zouridis, Laura Kistemaker and Morly Frishman, eds., The Hague,
Netherlands: Torkel Opsahi Academic Editor, forthcoming 2011).
1. Introduction.
We have been asked to consider, in a summary essay
form, three fundamental questions affecting the law-state in this century:
“What do you see as the most significant challenges
for the development of the law? What developments are we likely to see in the
coming two to three decades? What do those developments mean for national legal
systems in the international legal order as a whole?”
The questions put at issue, in a precise way, the
fundamental understanding of the basic building blocks of 20th century
socio-economic political culture—and particularly the character of law, the
state and non-state actors. But these questions also raise issues that are
dynamic and that implicate fundamental questions of institutional form,
function and legitimacy. Those issues revolve around communication, autonomy
and interdependence in the governance activities of state and non-state actors,
and the forms in which communication is undertaken, autonomy revealed and
interdependence manifested. There is
thus a dynamic element at the core of the questions that requires elaboration
and that serves as the urtext for
governance actors for this century. The thesis of this essay is this: Whatever
the outcome in the decades to come, states and their domestic legal orders will
not be able to maintain their isolation from the emerging non-national
governance frameworks and retain a substantial relevance; to avoid irrelevance,
states and their law systems must recognize governance polycentricism and more
effectively communicate with the emerging extra-legal governance frameworks of
public and private governance systems and by public and private actors. It is
that dynamic element of inter-systemic
harmonization and its challenges for that law-state that this essay
considers, weaving this theme within the three questions initially posed.
2. The Future: Divergence, Coordination, and Contradiction in
Ideologies of Convergence.
At
the start of the 21st century, governance harmonization has become a
more complicated, more desired, and yet more elusive enterprise. Even as the
enterprise of harmonization has grown, states have begun to more aggressively
resist harmonization as its ability to serve as a framework for the transfer of
governance power from states to new centres has been more widely felt. However,
that element of resistance has been complicated by the entry of new actors
within governance circles. Harmonization is currently proceeding simultaneously
along a number of different lines—horizontal, vertical and inter-systemic—that
reflects these ambiguous and multi-vector interactions and that also suggests
the context in which the future of legal systems, however understood, will be
determined.
Horizontal
harmonization occurs between entities (traditionally state entities) roughly
similarly situated within hierarchies of authorities—for example between the
states of the United States, between the Member States of the European Union,
or between two less formally connected states, for example between India and
Chile or between other states in the global community. It can be as simple a
project as finding a common language for communication and as complicated a
project as integrating legal systems. This push toward horizontal harmonization
of laws among sovereigns describes the great project of comparative law with
its origins in European 19th century notions of the state. Much that
passes for lawmaking remains at this level of 19th century
conceptions, even as the foundations for those conceptions—the superiority of
the state and of the positive law produced by a sovereign demos—has been
severely challenged. The challenges are
both horizontal and vertical.
Harmonization among states unequal in power or development is sometimes
understood either as a form of colonialism (a political undertaking through
law) or more insidiously, as a means of imposing the ideologies and political
choices of powerful states on less developed ones under the guise of simplicity,
communication and other virtues of legal harmonization. Even something as basic
as the linguistics of a language, can have ideological effects when transposed,
especially when words migrate from the legal cultures of developed states into
those of developing states. For example,
the migration of developed state notions of property imported into Brazil or
Panama to protect the rights of squatters on public lands has been used as a
vehicle for developers to deprive these dwellers of their properties through
sale or mortgage foreclosures.
The
monopoly of horizontal harmonization was broken in the aftermath of the World
Wars of the 20th century. After 1945 the focus increasingly shifted
from the state to a community of states, and from horizontal to vertical
harmonization. Vertical harmonization, that is the harmonization between
superior and inferior political entities, is less well developed and there is
no real consensus about its utility or legitimacy. Yet it is the central
element of the great 20th century project of legal
internationalization—and of the fundamental change in the understanding of the
state—now deeply embedded within an increasingly managed community of states.
The move towards internationalisation of standards and the communal management
of certain behaviours (by individuals, enterprises or states) through positive
law—corruption, human rights, and war—has become an important element of global
and transnational governance. The financial crisis of 2007-08 brought this
project into the foreground as the power of states, funnelled through the G-20
framework, sought to coordinate and channel state power through a supra-national
entity whose consensus views would then be adopted by all states. Transnational constitutionalism represents an
important form of efforts to undertake development of a customary practice of
vertical harmonization. The recent constitutional crisis in Honduras, and the
critical role played by international norms in resolving that domestic
constitutional crisis, provides a recent example of the development and growth
of this form of harmonization. Yet, the project of vertical harmonization
remains incomplete, and its fundamental premises continue to be challenged,
even as the great edifices of supra-national institutions are created and
public transnational law evolves.
However,
vertical harmonization continues to be grounded at its core in the state. Ironically, the great project of vertical
harmonization—economic globalisation—has also served to illuminate the
limitations of a state centred approach to law and harmonization. The 21st
century has witnessed the emergence of governance polycentricism, of the
potential broadening of the mechanics of law beyond the memorialisation of the
commands of territorially bounded states, of the rise of private law with
public functions and of public entities as private actors. This has substantially changed the landscape
of law. These changes have given rise to the most controversial form of
harmonization, at once the most interesting and potentially most far reaching
variant—inter-systemic harmonization,
or harmonization of public and private governance systems and by public and
private actors. States operating as
private enterprises in economic markets and economic entities serving as
substitutes for the state in weak governance zones suggests the context in
which public and private governance systems remain autonomous but communicate
and converge. The movement from customary and positive law to contract and the
governance mechanisms of surveillance expand and change the nature and
character of governance. The great projects
of sovereign investing by Norway and the People’s Republic of China through
their sovereign wealth funds provide examples of one of the forms that
inter-systemic harmonization is already taking. Sovereign investing integrates
systems of traditional state law making, public policy, administrative
mechanisms and participation in private markets to produce a comprehensive and
transnational approach to governance objectives.
These
changes both augment the power of states (with respect to the expansion of the
palette of legitimate governance tools) and shrink the scope of its control (as
other governance communities emerge with authority over actors operating within
the territory of states). The management of that convergence, communication and
interaction has been a great challenge for current efforts to harmonize
polycentric public-private systems, existing within states and outside of the
domestic legal order of any state.
Projects like that of John Ruggie’s business and human rights governance
framework—the Three Pillar Protect-Respect-Remedy Framework—provides a
contemporary application of these issues and serves as a harbinger of things to
come. Indeed, within the cluster of
governance issues understood as business and human rights, for example, the intersection
among domestic and international public legal orders, private governance
orders, the public role of private entities and the private role of public
entities become acute.
Consequently,
in place of the traditional focus on the law-state and its obsession with the
division between public and private, another focus is emerging, one in which
the comparative law project will need to bridge gaps between public law based
state systems and private social norm based systems. Just as lawmaking might
have become unmoored from the state, the state has itself become unmoored. And
so the issue of corporate citizenship serves as a proxy for the equally
important converse issues—that of the private rights of states as participants
in global markets. At the international level, states and other collectives
might well have to meet more as equals, even as they interact within vertical
hierarchies in particular contexts. But even those localized hierarchies are
now unstable. Corporations negotiate “agreements” with small states; nations
negotiate treaties. Large corporations can coerce small states in ways that
mimic the ways in which larger states can do the same to smaller and more
vulnerable ones. States and corporations are now capable of deploying forces in
the field—sometimes states hire corporations that serve as mercenary armies for
hire. The clear lines of public and private authority, and even the once clear
lines of its Marxist-Leninist opposite, have become blurred.
3. The Challenge for the Development of Law: Avoiding Containment
and Irrelevance.
The
construction and management of inter-relations between public and private
governance communities and the move from law to extra-legal systems of
behaviour control will serve as the great project of the 21st
century. As a consequence, the greatest challenge for law in the 21st
century is to avoid becoming irrelevant in an emerging global governance order
in which corporations use contracts to regulate their supply chains, states
reconstitute themselves as private market actors and private enterprises assert
regulatory control of markets through authoritative systems of assessment and
rating.
Consider
for example, the conventionally understood relationship between public and
private law. Private law has traditionally been understood to derive its power
and legitimacy from the state. It is attached to the state. The attachment of private law to the state
provides a strong ideological basis for the management of private relationships
by the state apparatus and the political community it represents. That attachment also suggested a place
outside of which law did not reach—but which was not considered legitimate or
legal, whatever its binding effect. And that was the end of it—as far as the
jurisdictional boundaries and legitimacy-dignity of law was understood to
extend. Thus, for example, with respect
to limits on the use of real property, the focus is on the individual common
law states, whose rights and obligations are mediated by the state through an
application of the law of nuisance. In
China, the same limits start from the obligations of individuals to the
community, memorialized in the great principles of Harmonious Society mediated
through the state apparatus under the leadership of the Communist Party. In theocratic systems, the focus is on the
community of the faithful whose collective obligations are mediated by a
priestly institution through religious law.
Beyond
the law of any of these variants lies a universe of morals, psychology, markets
and religion to which law was opaque (though was not above deploying discretely
from time to time through the device of “policy” focus, for example), and which
existed subject to the pre-emptive power of law. The ideology of law produced an incentive
towards autarchy totalitarianism in which the highest authority is
characterized as political and vested in territorially bounded states whose
legitimating organs (today democracy, yesterday anything from the Kaiser to the
priest) were solely vested with authority to bind all juridically recognized persons
within the state. The ideology of law
permitted a certain variation—sustaining the political framework of the United
States, the Soviet Union, Imperial Japan, and Nationalist Socialist Germany
simultaneously.
But
the 21st century has witnessed the rise of a new institutional
phenomenon—the functional detachment of
private law from the state. This suggests a fundamental reorientation of
governance, a movement away from the law-state binary to one grounded in the
law-norm binary (within which the state is not necessarily present). That
reorientation, in turn, suggests polycentricism, breaking the monopoly of power
exercised by the state producing positive law through democratically elected
institutions and reviving the autonomous force of custom. Yet this is custom of a non-traditional sort;
custom is now understood as producing rules that are given force through the
state apparatus (the traditional understanding of customary domestic law) but
it is also now understood as producing rules that memorialize the customs of
other governance communities, from multi-national corporations, to
supra-national actors. Law systems, in all their traditional variation, now
co-exist with the regulatory contract systems of multi-national corporations,
with the governance norms of transnational law-religion systems and with
supra-national organizations that produce and seek to enforce their own sets of
governance norms among their consenting members.
But
detachment also produces different forms of governance. Law tends to assume a
simple and single dimension form—a command to be obeyed, usually in the form of
an injunction to act or avoid acting in particular ways. However, the forms of
governance have expanded well beyond this simple and ancient technique. The movement
away from law to governance techniques has also made it easier for non-state
communities to develop an institutional framework and mechanics of effective
governance. Monitoring, surveillance, disclosure, standard setting, binding
principles, and objective evaluation techniques are among the methods of
governance that have acquired an increasing regulatory aspect. One can govern as effectively by fine-tuning
the classes of information required of an individual and providing consequences
for the results of the evaluation thereof, as by the command of a statute.
This
challenge to law suggests another—an institutional convergence in governance
capacity. Developed states and the
largest multinational corporations are closer in form and operation than either
is to less developed states and smaller corporations. Larger corporations and
developed states are then more likely to look to each other for governance
harmonization than either would look to developing states or smaller
corporations. That, in turn, suggests a fundamental reorientation of governance
chains grounded in a functional abandonment of the public-private distinction.
The resulting polycentricism becomes a powerful governance force as the
historical movement toward the assertion of near monopoly power by states
within their territories is reversed under the operative framework of economic
globalisation.
Opening
borders to commerce and investment has a strong collateral effect on the extent
of the empire of law as the operative instrument of the law-state. Open borders permit a disaggregation of
citizenship from residence, especially among investors and their investments.
It also produces a power in individuals to consent to membership in communities
with its own rules and institutional structures, whose objectives and functions
straddle multiple territorial borders.
Law now finds itself in a competitive environment of a force unseen
since the Enlightenment in Europe. On
the one hand, the character of law within states in changing. On the other, new techniques of law making
and porous borders have increased the sources of governance. Law, like the
state, has not so much been reduced in scope and power, as it has now come to
share governance space with a host of different institutions producing distinct
forms of command that may have some of the effects of traditional law but are
not law (classically understood as a legitimate command sourced in the
apparatus of a political state).
4. Toward a Mechanics of Relevance for National Legal Systems in the
International Legal Order as a Whole.
States
need not embrace the passive virtues of the philosophy of quietism. Indeed, it is essential for each state to not merely
rethink the basis of its legitimacy, form and function within its territory,
but also to stake out a space for its positive contribution within emerging
jurisdictional challenges posed by new governance frameworks, especially with
respect to its areas of control. The great challenge for states is to find a
way in which they might more actively engage in the processes of inter-systemic
and vertical harmonization without losing their fundamental character and
democratic connection with their citizens. That requires a willingness to
develop a domestic legal order that incorporates evolving international
standards that are themselves a product of the active participation of states
and other relevant stakeholders. This can work, for example, in the area of
corporate governance, in standards for bribery, and in the regulation of
conflict.
That
task requires a number of actions. First, states must not pout. States that
embrace insularity in the face of the emerging global polycentric governance
orders, states that raise walls of domestic legal systems around the borders of
their national territories (with the occasional extraterritorial foray) will,
quite perversely, increase the ability and ease with which other regulatory
actors might penetrate those barriers. The penetration would take advantage of
the blindness of law-states to governance frameworks beyond the state, that is,
they would take advantage of the limits inherent in the territorial borders
that once served more positively as a means for asserting a monopoly of state
power within them. Foreign multinational corporation regulation of host state
suppliers through contract provisions with little connection to the domestic
legal order of the host state, or the fidelity of host state actors to the
requirements of foreign supra-national evaluation and standard setting bodies
are examples of penetration that states would find difficult to prevent without
foregoing those connections that are almost invariably essential to the
well-being of its people.
Second,
states and their domestic legal orders will have to engage polycentricism
within their territories. That might require some flexibility in communicating
with autonomous systems and a willingness to harmonize their domestic legal
order with those of important parallel systems. This future is likely to be
represented by the governance communication and harmonization challenges faced
recently by a multinational corporation in the mining business, which found
itself in violation of the requirements of an autonomous international system
of norms for the conduct of its subsidiary, operating a mine through a
subsidiary jointly owned by it and a provincial government in the place where
the mine was located, despite the fact that the highest national court had
determined that the conduct at issue met all of the legal requirements imposed
by the state in which that mine was located.
States without sufficient points of contact with non-state governance
systems will find themselves isolated and less in control of the activities that
occur within their national territory.
Third,
the complexities of governance, and the dispersion of governance authority pose
institutional management problems for states.
One of the greatest is what John Ruggie has called problems of
incoherence. At the state level,
incoherence denotes the failure of communication and coordination of policy and
law making among the various ministries and regulatory agencies of a state
apparatus. The classic example is that of the South African Republic, whose
negotiation of bi-lateral investment treaty provisions by one ministry did not
take into account the requisites of human rights based policy being implemented
by another ministry. The resulting
conflicting obligations produced litigation to the detriment of state
policy. At the international level,
incoherence is more common and illustrated by the disjunction between the rules
applicable within a state through domestic law and the international
obligations of the state without direct domestic effect.
Fourth,
states must avoid legal segmentation. In the context of 19th century
global horizontal harmonization legal segmentation produces a harmonized law
for elites driven by the state and a local traditionalist law/custom for
everyone else. In places like Japan
before 1945 this produced a tendency towards multiple domestic legal orders
within a single territory. The same
effects are sometimes exhibited in developing states subject to significant
harmonization pressure through their entanglements with the global financial
community regulators—the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank. In the context of inter-systemic
harmonization, similar patterns produce a challenge of multiple domestic legal
orders that harmonize rules applicable, at least functionally, to distinct
segments of the national population. There is already evidence of this; China
exhibits a tendency toward bifurcated labour markets depending on whether
labour is hired for production within foreign dominated supply chains or
domestic ones. Bi-lateral investment
treaties create pockets of private law and rule making with respect to which
the domestic legal order may not play a decisive role.
Taken
together, these strategies suggest in the briefest form, the contours of the
challenges posed by inter-systemic harmonization, and the dangers of resisting
harmonization among these governance frameworks of “unequal” and distinctive
governance organs—states, intergovernmental organizations, transnational
private actors and multinational corporations and religions, to name only a
few. States seek to remain effective and powerful autonomous actors. The
expression of state power through law must remain vital. Yet these two objectives have become
complicated in a world in which states—and law—no longer occupy the governance
stage without competitors. States that can accommodate the new realities of
power diffusion and governance variety—of corporations that regulate, of states
that seek to project their power through traditionally private juridical persons
(corporations, transnational public and private organizations, and sovereign
investment funds), of functional law effectuated through survey, surveillance,
disclosure, standards, conditional income support programs, supply chain
relations, religious command and the like, are likely to be more effective
actors within and without their territories than those who hide from these
changes or resist them.
But
the processes of inter-systemic harmonization, like those of horizontal and
vertical harmonization, will neither be harmonious nor a rationally unfolding
well-managed process compelled by the power of its internal coherence and its
external incentives. The process will be
messy—and the results uneven. Vanguard states will become both more powerful
internally and more influential within global governance communities;
rejectionist states will seek to preserve traditional approaches in solidarity
with like minded states but become, in the process, less relevant globally. An important factor determining the extent of
conflict in moving to a world organized on principles of inter-systemic
harmonization, of course, and the effects of these transformations, are also
largely dependent on variations in state power. The least developed and least
powerful states (politically, culturally or economically) are likely to face
these challenges in a more direct and consequential form than the largest or
most powerful states. China and the United States can resist emerging trends
longer, and reach accommodations with the products of such trends in ways which
are impossible for the least developed African states. And indeed, in some
ways, and though it seeks to turn the process to advance its own interests,
China has already begun to move toward an inter-systemic harmonization model
more successfully than the United States. A most interesting set of challenges
face states that are already deeply enmeshed in supra-national governance
organizations. The Member States of the
European Union have greater experience in the dynamics of cooperation within
loosely bound normative structures. They also have experience in governance
within diffuse governance frameworks in which power is shared among a number of
stakeholders. Yet all of this diffusion
remains confined to the state and its supra-national creatures. Much can be
learned from the experience of Europe, though European states will have much to
learn, as well, from the experiences of developing states that confront the
power of transnational non-state governance.
Inter-systemic harmonization suggests the possibility that law might
preserve its relevance and autonomy. But it can achieve this objective only by
conceding its monopoly on governance.
__________
JOSE ERNESTO MEDELLIN,
Petitioner v. TEXAS
No. 06-984
SUPREME COURT
OF THE UNITED STATES
552 U.S. 491; 128 S. Ct.
1346; 170 L. Ed. 2d 190
October 10,
2007, Argued
March 25, 2008, Decided
March 25, 2008, Decided
[Available at: http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct/html/06-984.ZS.html]
Chief Justice Roberts
delivered the opinion of the Court.
The
International Court of Justice (ICJ), located in the Hague, is a tribunal
established pursuant to the United Nations Charter to adjudicate disputes
between member states. In the Case
Concerning Avena and Other Mexican Nationals (Mex. v. U.S.),
2004 I. C. J. 12 (Judgment of Mar. 31) (Avena), that tribunal considered
a claim brought by Mexico against the United States. The ICJ held that, based on violations of the
Vienna Convention, 51 named Mexican nationals were entitled to review and
reconsideration of their state-court convictions and sentences in the United
States. This was so regardless of any
forfeiture of the right to raise Vienna Convention claims because of a failure
to comply with generally applicable state rules governing challenges to criminal
convictions.
. .
. .
Petitioner Jose
Ernesto Medellin, who had been convicted and sentenced in Texas state court for
murder, is one of the 51 Mexican nationals named in the Avena
decision. Relying on the ICJ’s decision
and the President’s Memorandum, Medellin filed an application for a writ of
habeas corpus in state court. The Texas
Court of Criminal Appeals dismissed Medellin’s application as an abuse of the
writ under state law, given Medellin’s failure to raise his Vienna Convention
claim in a timely manner under state law.
We granted certiorari to decide two questions. First, is the ICJ’s judgment in Avena
directly enforceable as domestic law in a state court in the United
States? Second, does the
President’s Memorandum independently require the States to provide review and
reconsideration of the claims of the 51 Mexican nationals named in Avena
without regard to state procedural default rules? We conclude that neither Avena nor the
President’s Memorandum constitutes directly enforceable federal law that
pre-empts state limitations on the filing of successive habeas petitions. We therefore affirm the decision below.
I
A
In 1969, the
United States, upon the advice and consent of the Senate, ratified the Vienna
Convention on Consular Relations (Vienna Convention or Convention), Apr. 24,
1963, [1970] 21 U.S.T. 77, T. I. A. S. No. 6820, and the Optional Protocol
Concerning the Compulsory Settlement of Disputes to the Vienna Convention (Optional
Protocol or Protocol), Apr. 24, 1963, [1970] 21 U.S.T. 325, T. I. A. S. No.
6820. The preamble to the Convention
provides that its purpose is to “contribute to the development of friendly
relations among nations.”21 U.S.T., at 79; Sanchez-Llamas, supra, at 337,
126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557.
Toward that end, Article 36 of the Convention was drafted to
“facilitat[e] the exercise of consular functions.” Art. 36(1), 21 U.S.T., at 100. It provides that if a person detained by a
foreign country “so requests, the competent authorities of the receiving State
shall, without delay, inform the consular post of the sending State” of such
detention, and “inform the [detainee] of his righ[t]” to request assistance
from the consul of his own state. Art.
36(1)(b), id., at 101.
The Optional
Protocol provides a venue for the resolution of disputes arising out of the
interpretation or application of the Vienna Convention. Art. I, 21 U.S.T., at 326. Under the Protocol, such disputes “shall lie
within the compulsory jurisdiction of the International Court of Justice” and
“may accordingly be brought before the [ICJ] . . . by any party to the dispute
being a Party to the present Protocol.”Ibid.
The ICJ is “the
principal judicial organ of the United Nations.”United Nations Charter, Art.
92, 59 Stat. 1051, T. S. No. 993 (1945).
It was established in 1945 pursuant to the United Nations Charter. The ICJ Statute―annexed to the U. N.
Charter―provides the organizational framework and governing procedures for
cases brought before the ICJ. Statute of
the International Court of Justice (ICJ Statute), 59 Stat. 1055,, T. S. No. 993
(1945).
Under Article
94(1) of the U. N. Charter, “[e]ach Member of the United Nations undertakes to
comply with the decision of the [ICJ] in any case to which it is a party.”59
Stat. 1051. The ICJ’s jurisdiction in
any particular case, however, is dependent upon the consent of the
parties. See Art. 36, id., at
1060. The ICJ Statute delineates two
ways in which a nation may consent to ICJ jurisdiction: It may consent generally to jurisdiction on
any question arising under a treaty or general international law, Art. 36(2), ibid.,
or it may consent specifically to jurisdiction over a particular category of
cases or disputes pursuant to a separate treaty, Art. 36(1), ibid. The United States originally consented to the
general jurisdiction of the ICJ when it filed a declaration recognizing
compulsory jurisdiction under Art. 36(2) in 1946. The United States withdrew from general ICJ
jurisdiction in 1985. See U. S. Dept. of
State Letter and Statement Concerning Termination of Acceptance of ICJ
Compulsory Jurisdiction (Oct. 7, 1985), reprinted in 24 I. L. M. 1742 (1985).
By ratifying the Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention, the United States
consented to the specific jurisdiction of the ICJ with respect to claims
arising out of the Vienna Convention. On
March 7, 2005, subsequent to the ICJ’s judgment in Avena, the United
States gave notice of withdrawal from the
Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention. Letter from Condoleezza Rice, Secretary of
State, to Kofi A. Annan, Secretary-General of the United Nations.
B
Petitioner Jose
Ernesto Medellin, a Mexican national, has lived in the United States since
preschool. A member of the “Black and Whites” gang, Medellin was
convicted of capital murder and sentenced to death in Texas for the gang rape
and brutal murders of two Houston teenagers.
* *
*
Medellin was
arrested at approximately 4 a.m. on June 29, 1993. A few hours later, between 5:54 and 7:23
a.m., Medellin was given Miranda warnings; he then signed a written
waiver and gave a detailed written confession.
App. to Brief for Respondent 32-36.
Local law enforcement officers did not, however, inform Medellin of his
Vienna Convention right to notify the Mexican consulate of his detention. Brief for Petitioner 6-7. Medellin was convicted of capital murder and
sentenced to death; his conviction and sentence were affirmed on appeal. Medellin v. State, No. 71,997
(Tex. Crim. App., May 16, 1997), App. to Brief for Respondent 2-31.
Medellin first
raised his Vienna Convention claim in his first application for state post
conviction relief. The state trial court
held that the claim was procedurally defaulted because Medellin had failed to
raise it at trial or on direct review.
The trial court also rejected the Vienna Convention claim on the merits,
finding that Medellin had “fail[ed] to show that any non-notification of the
Mexican authorities impacted on the validity of his conviction or punishment.”Id.,
at 62. The Texas Court of Criminal
Appeals affirmed. Id., at 64-65.
. . . .
Medellin then
filed a habeas petition in Federal District Court. The District Court denied relief,
holding that Medellin’s Vienna
Convention claim was procedurally defaulted and that Medellin had failed to
show prejudice arising from the Vienna Convention violation. See Medellin v. Cockrell, 2003
U.S. Dist. LEXIS 27339, Civ. Action No. H-01-4078 (SD Tex., June 26, 2003),
App. to Brief for Respondent 66, 86-92.
While
Medellin’s application for a certificate of appealability was pending in the
Fifth Circuit, the ICJ issued its decision in Avena. The ICJ held that the United States had
violated Article 36(1)(b) of the Vienna Convention by failing to inform the 51
named Mexican nationals, including Medellin, of their Vienna Convention rights. 2004 I. C. J., at 53-55. In the ICJ’s determination, the United States
was obligated “to provide, by means of its own choosing, review and
reconsideration of the convictions and sentences of the [affected] Mexican
nationals.”Id., at 72, P 153(9)..
The ICJ indicated that such review was required without regard to state
procedural default rules. Id., at
56-57.
The Fifth
Circuit denied a certificate of appealability. . .
This Court
granted certiorari. Medellin v.
Dretke, 544 U.S. 660, 661, 125 S. Ct. 2088, 161 L. Ed. 2d 982 (2005) (per
curiam) (Medellin I). Before
we heard oral argument, however, President George W. Bush issued his Memorandum
for the United States Attorney General, providing:
“I have determined, pursuant to the
authority vested in me as President by the Constitution and the laws of the
United States of America, that the United States will discharge its
international obligations under the decision of the International Court of
Justice in [Avena], by having State courts give effect to the decision
in accordance with general principles of comity in cases filed by the 51
Mexican nationals addressed in that decision.”App. to Pet. for Cert. 187a.
Medellin,
relying on the President’s Memorandum and the ICJ’s decision in Avena,
filed a second application for habeas relief in state court. Ex parte Medellin, 223 S. W. 3d 315,
322-323 (Tex. Crim. App. 2006). . .
.
The Texas Court
of Criminal Appeals subsequently dismissed Medellin’s second state habeas
application as an abuse of the writ. 223
S. W. 3d, at 352. In the court’s
view, neither the Avena decision nor the President’s Memorandum was
“binding federal law” that could displace the State’s limitations on the filing
of successive habeas applications. Ibid. We again granted certiorari. 550 U.S. 917, 127 S. Ct. 2129, 167 L. Ed.
2d 862 (2007).
II
Medellin first
contends that the ICJ’s judgment in Avena constitutes a “binding”
obligation on the state and federal courts of the United States. He argues that “by virtue of the Supremacy
Clause, the treaties requiring compliance with the Avena judgment
are already the ‘Law of the Land’ by which all state and federal courts
in this country are ‘bound.’” Reply
Brief for Petitioner 1. Accordingly,
Medellin argues, Avena is a binding federal rule of decision that
pre-empts contrary state limitations on successive habeas petitions.
No one disputes
that the Avena decision―a decision that flows from the treaties through
which the United States submitted to ICJ jurisdiction with respect to Vienna
Convention disputes―constitutes an international law obligation on the
part of the United States. But not all
international law obligations automatically constitute binding federal law
enforceable in United States courts. The
question we confront here is whether the Avena judgment has automatic domestic
legal effect such that the judgment of its own force applies in state and
federal courts.
This Court has
long recognized the distinction between treaties that automatically have effect
as domestic law, and those that―while they constitute international law
commitments―do not by themselves function as binding federal law. The distinction was well explained by Chief
Justice Marshall’s opinion in Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet. 253,
315, 7 L. Ed. 415 (1829), overruled
on other grounds, United States v. Percheman, 32 U.S. 51, 7 Pet. 51, 8 L.
Ed. 604 (1833), which held that a treaty is “equivalent to an act of the
legislature,” and hence self-executing, when it “operates of itself without the
aid of any legislative provision.”Foster, supra, at 314, 2 Pet. 253, 315, 7
L. Ed. 415. When, in contrast,
“[treaty] stipulations are not self-executing they can only be enforced
pursuant to legislation to carry them into effect.”Whitney v. Robertson, 124
U.S. 190, 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed. 386 (1888). In sum, while treaties “may comprise
international commitments . . . they are not domestic law unless Congress has
either enacted implementing statutes or the treaty itself conveys an intention
that it be ‘self-executing’ and is ratified on these terms.”Igartua-De La
Rosa v. United States, 417 F.3d 145, 150 (CA1 2005) (en banc) (Boudin, C.
J.).
A treaty is, of
course, “primarily a compact between independent nations.”Head Money Cases,
112 U.S. 580, 598, 5 S. Ct. 247, 28 L. Ed. 798 (1884). It ordinarily “depends for the enforcement of
its provisions on the interest and the honor of the governments which are
parties to it.”Ibid.. . . . Only
“[i]f the treaty contains stipulations which are self-executing, that is,
require no legislation to make them operative, [will] they have the force and effect of a legislative enactment.”Whitney,
supra, at 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed. 386.
. . . .
Medellin and
his amici nonetheless contend that the Optional Protocol, United Nations
Charter, and ICJ Statute supply the “relevant obligation” to give the Avena
judgment binding effect in the domestic courts of the United States. Reply Brief for Petitioner 5-6.. . . .Because
none of these treaty sources creates binding federal law in the absence of implementing
legislation, and because it is uncontested that no such legislation exists, we
conclude that the Avena judgment is not automatically binding domestic
law.
A
The
interpretation of a treaty, like the interpretation of a statute, begins with
its text. Air France v. Saks, 470
U.S. 392, 396-397, 105 S. Ct. 1338, 84
L. Ed. 2d 289 (1985). Because a
treaty ratified by the United States is “an agreement among sovereign powers,”
we have also considered as “aids to its interpretation” the negotiation and drafting
history of the treaty as well as “the post ratification understanding” of
signatory nations. Zicherman v.
Korean Air Lines Co., 516 U.S. 217, 226, 116 S. Ct. 629, 133 L. Ed. 2d 596
(1996). . . .
As a signatory
to the Optional Protocol, the United States agreed to submit disputes arising
out of the Vienna Convention to the ICJ.
The Protocol provides: “Disputes
arising out of the interpretation or application of the [Vienna] Convention
shall lie within the compulsory jurisdiction of the International Court of
Justice.” Art. I, 21 U.S.T., at
326. Of course, submitting to
jurisdiction and agreeing to be bound are two different things. A party could, for example, agree to
compulsory nonbinding arbitration. Such
an agreement would require the party to
appear before the arbitral tribunal without obligating the party to treat the
tribunal’s decision as binding. See, e.g.,
North American Free Trade Agreement, U. S.-Can.-Mex., Art. 2018(1), Dec. 17,
1992, 32 I. L. M. 605, 697 (1993) (“On receipt of the final report of [the
arbitral panel requested by a Party to the agreement], the disputing Parties
shall agree on the resolution of the dispute, which normally shall conform with
the determinations and recommendations of the panel”).
The most
natural reading of the Optional Protocol is as a bare grant of
jurisdiction. It provides only that
“[d]isputes arising out of the interpretation or application of the [Vienna]
Convention shall lie within the compulsory jurisdiction of the International
Court of Justice” and “may accordingly be brought before the [ICJ] . . . by any
party to the dispute being a Party to the present Protocol.” Art. I, 21 U.S.T., at 326. The Protocol says nothing about the effect of
an ICJ decision and does not itself commit signatories to comply with an ICJ judgment. The Protocol is similarly silent as to any
enforcement mechanism.
The obligation
on the part of signatory nations to comply with ICJ judgments derives not from
the Optional Protocol, but rather from Article 94 of the United Nations
Charter―the provision that specifically addresses the effect of ICJ decisions. [13] Article 94(1) provides that “[e]ach
Member of the United Nations undertakes to comply with the decision of
the [ICJ] in any case to which it is a party.”
59 Stat. 1051 (emphasis added).
The Executive Branch contends that the phrase “undertakes to comply” is
not “an acknowledgement that an ICJ decision will have immediate legal effect
in the courts of U. N. members,” but rather “a commitment on the part of
U. N. members to take future action through their political branches to
comply with an ICJ decision.” Brief for
United States as Amicus Curiae in Medellin I, O. T. 2004, No.
04-5928, p 34.
We agree with
this construction of Article 94. The
Article is not a directive to domestic courts.
It does not provide that the United States “shall” or “must” comply with
an ICJ decision, nor indicate that the Senate that ratified the U. N. Charter
intended to vest ICJ decisions with immediate legal effect in domestic
courts. Instead, “[t]he words of Article
94 . . . call upon governments to take certain action.”Committee of United
States Citizens Living in Nicaragua v. Reagan, 273 U.S. App. D.C. 266, 859 F.2d
929, 938 (CADC 1988) (quoting Diggs v. Richardson, 180 U.S. App. D.C.
376, 555 F.2d 848, 851 (CADC 1976); internal quotation marks omitted). . . . .
In other words, the U. N. Charter reads like “a compact between
independent nations” that “depends for the enforcement of its provisions on the
interest and the honor of the
governments which are parties to it.”Head Money Cases, 112 U.S., at 598, 5
S. Ct. 247, 28 L. Ed. 798.
The remainder
of Article 94 confirms that the U. N.
Charter does not contemplate the automatic enforceability of ICJ decisions in
domestic courts.. . . Article 94(2)―the
enforcement provision―provides the sole remedy for noncompliance: referral to the United Nations Security
Council by an aggrieved state. 59 Stat.
1051.
The U. N.
Charter’s provision of an express diplomatic―that is, nonjudicial―remedy is
itself evidence that ICJ judgments were not meant to be enforceable in domestic
courts. See Sanchez-Llamas, 548 U.S.,
at 347, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557.
And even this “quintessentially internationalremed[y],”id., at
355, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557, is not absolute. First, the Security Council must “dee[m]
necessary” the issuance of a recommendation or measure to effectuate the
judgment. Art. 94(2), 59 Stat.
1051. Second, as the President and
Senate were undoubtedly aware in subscribing to the U. N. Charter and Optional
Protocol, the United States retained the
unqualified right to exercise its veto of any Security Council resolution.
This was the
understanding of the Executive Branch when the President agreed to the U. N.
Charter and the declaration accepting general compulsory ICJ jurisdiction. . . . .
If ICJ
judgments were instead regarded as automatically enforceable domestic law, they
would be immediately and directly binding on state and federal courts pursuant
to the Supremacy Clause. Mexico
or the ICJ would have no need to proceed
to the Security Council to enforce the judgment in this case. Noncompliance with an ICJ judgment through
exercise of the Security Council veto―always regarded as an option by the
Executive and ratifying Senate during and after consideration of the U. N.
Charter, Optional Protocol, and ICJ Statute―would no longer be a viable
alternative. There would be nothing to
veto. In light of the U. N. Charter’s
remedial scheme, there is no reason to believe that the President and Senate
signed up for such a result.
In sum,
Medellin’s view that ICJ decisions are automatically enforceable as domestic
law is fatally undermined by the enforcement structure established by Article
94. His construction would eliminate the
option of noncompliance contemplated by Article 94(2), undermining the ability
of the political branches to determine whether and how to comply with an ICJ
judgment. Those sensitive foreign policy
decisions would instead be transferred to state and federal courts charged with
applying an ICJ judgment directly as domestic law. And those courts would not be empowered to
decide whether to comply with the judgment―again, always regarded as an option
by the political branches―any more than courts may consider whether to comply
with any other species of domestic law.
This result would be particularly anomalous in light of the principle
that “[t]he conduct of the foreign relations of our Government is committed by
the Constitution to the Executive and Legislative―’the political’―Departments.”Oetjen
v. Central Leather Co., 246 U.S. 297, 302, 38 S. Ct. 309, 62 L. Ed. 726 (1918).
. .
. .
Medellin argues
that because the Avena case involves him, it is clear that he―and the 50
other Mexican nationals named in the Avena decision―should be regarded
as parties to the Avena judgment.
Brief for Petitioner 21-22. But
cases before the ICJ are often precipitated by disputes involving particular
persons or entities, disputes that a nation elects to take up as its own. . . .
. That has never been understood to
alter the express and established rules that only nation-states may be parties
before the ICJ, Art. 34, 59 Stat. 1059, and―contrary to the position of the
dissent, post, at ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 244―that ICJ judgments are
binding only between those parties, Art. 59, Stat. 1062.
. .
. .
It is,
moreover, well settled that the United States’ interpretation of a treaty “is
entitled to great weight.”Sumitomo Shoji America, Inc. v. Avagliano, 457
U.S. 176, 184-185, 102 S. Ct. 2374, 72 L. Ed. 2d 765 (1982). . . . The Executive Branch has unfailingly adhered
to its view that the relevant treaties do not create domestically enforceable
federal law. See Brief for United States
as Amicus Curiae 4, 27-29.
. . . .
The pertinent
international agreements, therefore, do not provide for implementation of ICJ
judgments through direct enforcement in domestic courts, and “where a treaty
does not provide a particular remedy, either expressly or implicitly, it is not for the federal courts to impose one
on the States through lawmaking of their own.”Sanchez-Llamas, 548 U.S., at
347, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557.
B
The dissent
faults our analysis because it “looks for the wrong thing (explicit textual
expression about self-execution) using the wrong standard (clarity) in the
wrong place (the treaty language).”Post, at ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 246. Given our obligation to interpret treaty
provisions to determine whether they are self-executing, we have to confess
that we do think it rather important to look to the treaty language to see what
it has to say about the issue. That is
after all what the Senate looks to in deciding whether to approve the treaty.
The
interpretive approach employed by the Court today―resorting to the text―is
hardly novel. In two early cases
involving an 1819 land-grant treaty between Spain and the United States, Chief
Justice Marshall found the language of the treaty dispositive. In Foster, after distinguishing
between self-executing treaties (those “equivalent to an act of the
legislature”) and non-self-executing treaties (those “the legislature must
execute”), Chief Justice Marshall held that the 1819 treaty was
non-self-executing. 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet., at 314, 7 L. Ed. 415. Four years later, the Supreme Court
considered another claim under the same treaty, but concluded that the treaty
was self-executing. See Percheman, 32
U.S. 51, 7 Pet., at 87, 8 L. Ed. 604.
The reason was not because the treaty was sometimes self-executing and
sometimes not, but because “the language of” the Spanish translation (brought
to the Court’s attention for the first time) indicated the parties’ intent to
ratify and confirm the land-grant “by force of the instrument itself.”Id.,
32 U.S. 51, 7 Pet., at 89, 8 L. Ed. 604.
As against this
time-honored textual approach, the dissent proposes a multifactor,
judgment-by-judgment analysis that would “jettiso[n] relative predictability
for the open-ended rough-and-tumble of factors.”Jerome B. Grubart, Inc.
v.Great Lakes Dredge & Dock Co., 513 U.S. 527, 547, 115 S. Ct. 1043, 130 L.
Ed. 2d 1024 (1995). The dissent’s
novel approach to deciding which (or, more accurately, when) treaties give rise
to directly enforceable federal law is arrestingly indeterminate. Treaty language is barely probative. Post,
at ____ - ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 237-238 (“[T]he absence or presence of
language in a treaty about a provision’s self-execution proves nothing at
all”). Determining whether treaties
themselves create federal law is sometimes committed to the political branches
and sometimes to the judiciary. Post, at ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 238-246. Of those committed to the judiciary, the
courts pick and choose which shall be binding United States law―trumping not
only state but other federal law as well―and which shall not. Post, at ____
- ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 238. They
do this on the basis of a multifactor, “context-specific” inquiry. Post, at
____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 238. Even
then, the same treaty sometimes gives rise to United States law and sometimes
does not, again depending on an ad hoc judicial assessment. Post, at ____ -
____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 238-246.
Our Framers
established a careful set of procedures that must be followed before federal
law can be created under the Constitution―vesting that decision in the
political branches, subject to checks and balances. U.S. Const., Art. I, § 7. They also recognized that treaties could
create federal law, but again through the political branches, with the
President making the treaty and the
Senate approving it. Art. II, § 2. The dissent’s understanding of the treaty
route, depending on an ad hoc judgment of the judiciary without looking to the
treaty language―the very language negotiated by the President and approved by
the Senate―cannot readily be ascribed to those same Framers.
The dissent’s
approach risks the United States’ involvement in international agreements. It is hard to believe that the United States
would enter into treaties that are sometimes enforceable and sometimes not. Such a treaty would be the equivalent of
writing a blank check to the judiciary.
Senators could never be quite sure what the treaties on which they were
voting meant. Only a judge could say for
sure and only at some future date. This
uncertainty could hobble the United
States’ efforts to negotiate and sign international agreements.
In this case,
the dissent―for a grab bag of no less than seven reasons―would tell us that
this particular ICJ judgment is federal law. Post, at ____ - ____,
170 L. Ed. 2d, at 238-246. That is
no sort of guidance.
Nor is it any
answer to say that the federal courts will diligently police international
agreements and enforce the decisions of international tribunals only when they should
be enforced. Ibid. The point
of a non-self-executing treaty is that it “addresses itself to the political, not
the judicial department; and the legislature must execute the contract before
it can become a rule for the Court.”Foster, 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet., at 314, 7
L. Ed. 415 (emphasis added); Whitney, 124 U.S., at 195,8 S. Ct. 456, 31
L. Ed. 386. See also Foster, 27
U.S. 253, 2 Pet. , at 307, 7 L. Ed. 415 (“The judiciary is not that
department of the government, to which the assertion of its interests against
foreign powers is confided”). The
dissent’s contrary approach would assign to the courts―not the political
branches―the primary role in deciding when and how international agreements
will be enforced. To read a treaty so
that it sometimes has the effect of domestic law and sometimes does not is tantamount
to vesting with the judiciary the power not only to interpret but also to
create the law.
C
Our conclusion
that Avena does not by itself constitute binding federal law is
confirmed by the “post ratification understanding” of signatory nations. See Zicherman, 516 U.S., at 226, 116 S.
Ct. 629, 133 L. Ed. 2d 596. There
are currently 47 nations that are parties to the Optional Protocol and 171
nations that are parties to the Vienna Convention. Yet neither Medellin nor his amici
have identified a single nation that treats ICJ judgments as binding in
domestic courts. . . . .
Our conclusion
is further supported by general principles of interpretation. To begin with, we reiterated in Sanchez-Llamas
what we held in Breard, that “‘absent a clear and express statement to
the contrary, the procedural rules of the forum State govern the implementation
of the treaty in that State.’”548 U.S., at 351, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed.
2d 557 (quoting Breard, 523 U.S., at 375, 118 S. Ct. 1352, 140 L. Ed. 2d
529). Given that ICJ judgments may
interfere with state procedural rules, one would expect the ratifying parties
to the relevant treaties to have clearly stated their intent to give those
judgments domestic effect, if they had so intended. Here there is no statement in the Optional
Protocol, the U. N. Charter, or the ICJ Statute that supports the notion that
ICJ judgments displace state procedural rules.
Moreover, the
consequences of Medellin’s argument give pause.
An ICJ judgment, the argument goes, is not only binding domestic law but
is also unassailable. As a result,
neither Texas nor this Court may look behind a judgment and quarrel with its
reasoning or result. (We already know,
from Sanchez-Llamas, that this Court disagrees with both the reasoning and result in Avena.)
Medellin’s interpretation would allow ICJ judgments to override otherwise
binding state law; there is nothing in his logic that would exempt contrary
federal law from the same fate. See, e.g.,
Cook v. United States, 288 U.S. 102, 119, 53 S. Ct. 305, 77 L. Ed. 641 (1933)
(later-in-time self-executing treaty supersedes a federal statue if there is a
conflict). And there is nothing to
prevent the ICJ from ordering state courts to annul criminal convictions and
sentences, for any reason deemed sufficient by the ICJ. Indeed, that is precisely the relief Mexico
requested. Avena, 2004 I. C. J., at 58-59.
Even the dissent
flinches at reading the relevant treaties to give rise to self-executing ICJ
judgments in all cases. . . .
In short, and
as we observed in Sanchez-Llamas, “[n]othing in the structure or purpose
of the ICJ suggests that its interpretations were intended to be conclusive on
our courts.”548 U.S., at 354, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557. Given that holding, it is difficult to see
how that same structure and purpose can establish, as Medellin argues, that judgments
of the ICJ nonetheless were intended to be conclusive on our courts. A judgment is binding only if there is a rule
of law that makes it so. And the
question whether ICJ judgments can bind domestic courts depends upon the same
analysis undertaken in Sanchez-Llamas and set forth above.
Our prior
decisions identified by the dissent as holding a number of treaties to be
self-executing, see post, at ____ - ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 235, and
Appendix A, stand only for the unremarkable proposition that some international
agreements are self-executing and others are not. . . .
We do not
suggest that treaties can never afford binding domestic effect to international
tribunal judgments―only that the U. N. Charter, the Optional Protocol, and the
ICJ Statute do not do so. And whether
the treaties underlying a judgment are self-executing so that the judgment is
directly enforceable as domestic law in our courts is, of course, a matter for
this Court to decide. See Sanchez-Llamas,
supra, at 353-354, 126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557.
D
Our holding
does not call into question the ordinary enforcement of foreign judgments or
international arbitral agreements.
Indeed, we agree with Medellin that, as a general matter, “an agreement
to abide by the result” of an international adjudication―or what he really
means, an agreement to give the result of such adjudication domestic legal
effect ―can be a treaty obligation like any other, so long as the agreement is
consistent with the Constitution. See
Brief for Petitioner 20. The point is
that the particular treaty obligations on which Medellin relies do not of their
own force create domestic law.
. .
. .
Further, that
an ICJ judgment may not be automatically enforceable in domestic courts does
not mean the particular underlying treaty is not. Indeed, we have held that a number of the
“Friendship, Commerce, and Navigation” Treaties cited by the dissent, see post,
Appendix B, are self-executing―based on “the language of the[se]
Treat[ies].” See Sumitomo Shoji
America, Inc., supra, at 180, 189-190, 102 S. Ct. 2374, 72 L. Ed. 2d 765. In Kolovrat v. Oregon, 366 U.S. 187, 191, 196, 81 S. Ct.
922, 6 L. Ed. 2d 218 (1961), for example, the Court found that Yugoslavian
claimants denied inheritance under Oregon law were entitled to inherit personal
property pursuant to an 1881 Treaty of Friendship, Navigation, and Commerce
between the United States and Serbia.
See also Clark v. Allen, 331 U.S. 503, 507-511, 517-518, 67 S. Ct.
1431, 91 L. Ed. 1633 (1947) (finding that the right to inherit real
property granted German aliens under the Treaty of Friendship, Commerce and
Consular Rights with Germany prevailed over California law). Contrary to the dissent’s suggestion, see post,
at ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 236-237, neither our approach nor our cases
require that a treaty provide for self-execution in so many talismanic words;
that is a caricature of the Court’s opinion.
Our cases simply require courts to decide whether a treaty’s terms
reflect a determination by the President who negotiated it and the Senate that
confirmed it that the treaty has domestic effect.
In addition,
Congress is up to the task of implementing non-self-executing treaties, even
those involving complex commercial disputes.
Cf. post, at ____, 170 L. Ed. 2d, at 244 (Breyer, J.,
dissenting). The judgments of a number
of international tribunals enjoy a different status because of implementing
legislation enacted by Congress. . . .
Such language demonstrates that Congress knows how to accord domestic
effect to international obligations when it desires such a result.
Further,
Medellin frames his argument as though giving the Avena judgment binding
effect in domestic courts simply conforms to the proposition that domestic
courts generally give effect to foreign judgments. But Medellin does not ask us to enforce a
foreign-court judgment settling a typical commercial or property dispute. . .
. What is more, on Medellin’s view, the
judgment would force the State to take action to “review and reconside[r]” his
case. The general rule, however, is that
judgments of foreign courts awarding injunctive relief, even as to private
parties, let alone sovereign States, “are not generally entitled to
enforcement.” See 1 Restatement §
481, Comment b, at 595.
In sum, while
the ICJ’s judgment in Avena creates an international law obligation on
the part of the United States, it does not of its own force constitute binding
federal law that pre-empts state
restrictions on the filing of successive habeas petitions. As we noted in Sanchez-Llamas, a
contrary conclusion would be extraordinary, given that basic rights guaranteed
by our own Constitution do not have the effect of displacing state procedural
rules. See 548 U.S., at 360, 126 S.
Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557. Nothing in the text, background, negotiating
and drafting history, or practice among signatory nations suggests that the
President or Senate intended the improbable result of giving the judgments of
an international tribunal a higher status than that enjoyed by “many of our most
fundamental constitutional protections.”Ibid.
III
Medellin next
argues that the ICJ’s judgment in Avena is binding on state courts by
virtue of the President’s February 28, 2005 Memorandum. The United States contends that while the Avena
judgment does not of its own force require domestic courts to set aside
ordinary rules of procedural default, that judgment became the law of the land
with precisely that effect pursuant to the President’s Memorandum and his power
“to establish binding rules of decision that
preempt contrary state law.”Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae
5. Accordingly, we must decide whether
the President’s declaration alters our conclusion that the Avena
judgment is not a rule of domestic law binding in state and federal courts. . .
.
A
The United
States maintains that the President’s constitutional role “uniquely qualifies”
him to resolve the sensitive foreign
policy decisions that bear on compliance with an ICJ decision and “to do so
expeditiously.”Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 11, 12. We do not question these propositions. . . . .
In this case, the President seeks to vindicate United States interests
in ensuring the reciprocal observance of the Vienna Convention, protecting
relations with foreign governments, and demonstrating commitment to the role of
international law. These interests are
plainly compelling.
Such considerations, however, do not allow us
to set aside first principles. The
President’s authority to act, as with the exercise of any governmental power,
“must stem either from an act of Congress or from the Constitution itself.”Youngstown,
supra, at 585, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417; Dames
& Moore v. Regan, 453 U.S. 654, 668, 101 S. Ct. 2972, 69 L. Ed. 2d 918
(1981).
Justice Jackson’s
familiar tripartite scheme provides the accepted framework for evaluating
executive action in this area. First,
“[w]hen the President acts pursuant to an express or implied authorization of
Congress, his authority is at its maximum, for it includes all that he
possesses in his own right plus all that Congress can delegate.”Youngstown,
343 U.S., at 635, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417
(opinion concurring). Second, “[w]hen
the President acts in absence of either a congressional grant or denial of
authority, he can only rely upon his own independent powers, but there is a
zone of twilight in which he and Congress may have concurrent authority, or in
which its distribution is uncertain.”Id., at 637, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed.
1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 In this circumstance, Presidential authority can
derive support from “congressional inertia, indifference or quiescence.”Ibid. Finally, “[w]hen the President takes
measures incompatible with the expressed or implied will of Congress, his power
is at its lowest ebb,” and the Court can
sustain his actions “only by disabling the Congress from acting upon the
subject.”Id., at 637-638, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs.
417
B
The United
States marshals two principal arguments in favor of the President’s authority
“to establish binding rules of decision that preempt contrary state law.”Brief
for United States as Amicus Curiae 5.
The Solicitor General first argues that the relevant treaties give the
President the authority to implement the Avena judgment and that
Congress has acquiesced in the exercise of such authority. The United States also relies upon an
“independent” international dispute-resolution power wholly apart from the
asserted authority based on the pertinent treaties. Medellin adds the additional argument that
the President’s Memorandum is a valid exercise of his power to take care that
the laws be faithfully executed.
1
The United
States maintains that the President’s Memorandum is authorized by the Optional
Protocol and the U. N. Charter. Brief
for United States as Amicus Curiae 9.
That is, because the relevant treaties “create an obligation to comply
with Avena,” they “implicitly give the President authority to
implement that treaty-based obligation.”Id., at 11 (emphasis
added). As a result, the President’s
Memorandum is well grounded in the first category of the Youngstown
framework.
We
disagree. The President has an array of
political and diplomatic means available to enforce international obligations,
but unilaterally converting a non-self-executing treaty into a self-executing
one is not among them. The
responsibility for transforming an international obligation arising from a
non-self-executing treaty into domestic law falls to Congress. Foster, 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet., at
315, 7 L. Ed. 415; Whitney, 124 U.S., at 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed.
386; Igartua-De La Rosa, 417 F.3d at 150.
. .
. . .
A
non-self-executing treaty, by definition, is one that was ratified with the
understanding that it is not to have domestic effect of its own force. That understanding precludes the assertion
that Congress has implicitly authorized the President ―acting on his own―to
achieve precisely the same result. We
therefore conclude, given the absence of congressional legislation, that the
non-self-executing treaties at issue here did not “express[ly] or implied[ly]”
vest the President with the unilateral authority to make them
self-executing. See id., at 635, 72
S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 (Jackson, J.,
concurring). Accordingly, the
President’s Memorandum does not fall within the first category of the Youngstown
framework.
Indeed, the
preceding discussion should make clear that the non-self-executing character of
the relevant treaties not only refutes the notion that the ratifying parties
vested the President with the authority to unilaterally make treaty obligations
binding on domestic courts, but also implicitly prohibits him from doing
so. When the President asserts the power
to “enforce” a non-self-executing treaty by unilaterally creating domestic law,
he acts in conflict with the implicit understanding of the ratifying
Senate. His assertion of authority,
insofar as it is based on the pertinent non-self-executing treaties, is
therefore within Justice Jackson’s third category, not the first or even the
second. See id., at 637-638, 72 S.
Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417.
. .
. .
The United
States nonetheless maintains that the President’s Memorandum should be given
effect as domestic law because “this case involves a valid Presidential action
in the context of Congressional ‘acquiescence.’” Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae
11, n 2. Under the Youngstown
tripartite framework, congressional acquiescence is pertinent when the
President’s action falls within the second category―that is, when he “acts in
absence of either a congressional grant or denial of authority.”343 U.S., at
637, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 (Jackson, J.,
concurring). Here, however, as we have
explained, the President’s effort to accord domestic effect to the Avena
judgment does not meet that prerequisite.
In any event,
even if we were persuaded that congressional acquiescence could support the
President’s asserted authority to create domestic law pursuant to a
non-self-executing treaty, such acquiescence does not exist here. The United States first locates congressional
acquiescence in Congress’s failure to act following the President’s resolution
of prior ICJ controversies. A review of
the Executive’s actions in those prior cases, however, cannot support the claim
that Congress acquiesced in this particular exercise of Presidential authority,
for none of them remotely involved transforming an international obligation
into domestic law and thereby displacing state law. . . . . ..
The United
States also directs us to the President’s “related” statutory responsibilities
and to his “established role” in litigating foreign policy concerns as support
for the President’s asserted authority to give the ICJ’s decision in Avena
the force of domestic law. Brief for
United States as Amicus Curiae 16-19.
Congress has indeed authorized the President to represent the United
States before the United Nations, the ICJ, and the Security Council, 22
U.S.C. § 287, but the authority of the President to represent the
United States before such bodies speaks to the President’s international
responsibilities, not any unilateral authority to create domestic law. The authority expressly conferred by Congress
in the international realm cannot be said to “invite” the Presidential action
at issue here. See Youngstown, supra,
at 637, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 (Jackson, J.,
concurring). At bottom, none of the
sources of authority identified by the United States supports the President’s
claim that Congress has acquiesced in his asserted power to establish on his
own federal law or to override state law.
None of this is
to say, however, that the combination of a non-self-executing treaty and the
lack of implementing legislation preclude the President from acting to comply
with an international treaty obligation.
It is only to say that the Executive cannot unilaterally execute a
non-self-executing treaty by giving it domestic effect. That is, the non-self-executing character of
a treaty constrains the President’s ability to comply with treaty commitments
by unilaterally making the treaty binding on domestic courts. The President may comply with the treaty’s
obligations by some other means, so long as they are consistent with the
Constitution. But he may not rely upon a
non-self-executing treaty to “establish binding rules of decision that preempt
contrary state law.”Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 5.
2
We thus turn to
the United States’ claim that―independent of the United States’ treaty
obligations―the Memorandum is a valid exercise of the President’s foreign
affairs authority to resolve claims disputes with foreign nations. Id., at 12-16. The United States relies on a series of cases
in which this Court has upheld the authority of the President to settle foreign
claims pursuant to an executive agreement.
See Garamendi, 539 U.S., at 415, 123 S. Ct. 2374, 156 L. Ed. 2d 376;
Dames & Moore, 453 U.S., at 679-680, 101 S. Ct. 2972, 69 L. Ed. 2d 918;
United States v. Pink, 315 U.S. 203, 229, 62 S. Ct. 552, 86 L. Ed. 796
(1942); United States v. Belmont,
301 U.S. 324, 330, 57 S. Ct. 758, 81 L. Ed. 1134 (1937). In these cases this Court has explained that,
if pervasive enough, a history of congressional acquiescence can be treated as
a “gloss on ‘Executive Power’ vested in the President by § 1 of Art. II.”Dames
& Moore, supra, at 686, 101 S. Ct. 2972, 69 L. Ed. 2d 918 (some
internal quotation marks omitted).
This argument
is of a different nature than the one rejected above. Rather than relying on the United States’
treaty obligations, the President relies on an independent source of authority
in ordering Texas to put aside its procedural bar to successive habeas
petitions. Nevertheless, we find that our claims-settlement cases do not
support the authority that the President asserts in this case.
. .
. .
Even still, the
limitations on this source of executive power are clearly set forth and the
Court has been careful to note that “[p]ast practice does not, by itself,
create power.”Dames & Moore, supra, at 686, 101 S. Ct. 2972, 69 L. Ed.
2d 918.
The President’s
Memorandum is not supported by a “particularly longstanding practice” of
congressional acquiescence, see Garamendi, supra, at 415,123 S. Ct. 2374,
156 L. Ed. 2d 376, but rather is what the United States itself has
described as “unprecedented action,” Brief for United States as Amicus
Curiae in Sanchez-Llamas, O. T. 2005, Nos. 05-51 and 04-10566, pp
29-30. Indeed, the Government has not
identified a single instance in which the President has attempted (or Congress
has acquiesced in) a Presidential directive issued to state courts, much less
one that reaches deep into the heart of the State’s police powers and compels
state courts to reopen final criminal judgments and set aside neutrally
applicable state laws. Cf. Brecht v.
Abrahamson, 507 U.S. 619, 635, 113 S. Ct. 1710, 123 L. Ed. 2d 353 (1993)“States
possess primary authority for defining and enforcing the criminal law” (quoting
Engle v. Isaac, 456 U.S. 107, 128, 102 S. Ct. 1558, 71 L. Ed. 2d 783 (1982);
internal quotation marks omitted). The
Executive’s narrow and strictly limited authority to settle international
claims disputes pursuant to an executive agreement cannot stretch so far as to
support the current Presidential Memorandum.
3
Medellin argues
that the President’s Memorandum is a valid exercise of his “[T]ake Care”
power. Brief for Petitioner 28. The United States, however, does not rely
upon the President’s responsibility to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully
executed.”U.S. Const., Art. II, § 3.
We think this a wise concession.
This authority allows the President to execute the laws, not make
them. For the reasons we have stated,
the Avena judgment is not domestic law; accordingly, the President
cannot rely on his Take Care powers here.
The judgment of
the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals is affirmed.
It is so
ordered.
447 U.S. 74
PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins
PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins
APPEAL
FROM THE SUPREME COURT OF CALIFORNIA
No.
79-289 Argued: March 18, 1980 ―- Decided: June 9, 1980
[Available at: http://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/447/74/case.html]
[Available at: http://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/447/74/case.html]
MR.
JUSTICE REHNQUIST delivered the opinion of the Court.
We postponed
jurisdiction of this appeal from the Supreme Court of California to decide the
important federal constitutional questions it presented. Those are whether
state constitutional provisions, which permit individuals to exercise free
speech and petition rights on the property of a privately owned shopping center
to which the public is invited, violate the shopping center owner’s property
rights under the Fifth [p77] and Fourteenth Amendments or his
free speech rights under the First and Fourteenth Amendments.
I
Appellant
PruneYard is a privately owned shopping center in the City of Campbell, Cal. It
covers approximately 21 acres ― 5 devoted to parking and 16 occupied by
walkways, plazas, sidewalks, and buildings that contain more than 65 specialty
shops, 10 restaurants, and a movie theater. The PruneYard is open to the public
for the purpose of encouraging the patronizing of its commercial
establishments. It has a policy not to permit any visitor or tenant to engage
in any publicly expressive activity, including the circulation of petitions,
that is not directly related to its commercial purposes. This policy has been
strictly enforced in a nondiscriminatory fashion. The PruneYard is owned by
appellant Fred Sahadi.
Appellees are
high school students who sought to solicit support for their opposition to a
United Nations resolution against “Zionism.” On a Saturday afternoon they set
up a card table in a corner of PruneYard’s central courtyard. They distributed
pamphlets and asked passersby to sign petitions, which were to be sent to the
President and Members of Congress. Their activity was peaceful and orderly,
and, so far as the record indicates, was not objected to by PruneYard’s
patrons.
Soon after appellees
had begun soliciting signatures, a security guard informed them that they would
have to leave because their activity violated PruneYard regulations. The guard
suggested that they move to the public sidewalk at the PruneYard’s perimeter.
Appellees immediately left the premises and later filed this lawsuit in the
California Superior Court of Santa Clara County. They sought to enjoin
appellants from denying them access to the PruneYard for the purpose of
circulating their petitions.
The Superior
Court held that appellees were not entitled under either the Federal or
California Constitution to exercise [p78] their asserted rights on the
shopping center property. App. to Juris.Statement A-2. It concluded that there
were “adequate, effective channels of communication for [appellees] other than
soliciting on the private property of the [PruneYard].”Id. at A-3. The
California Court of Appeal affirmed.
The California
Supreme Court reversed, holding that the California Constitution protects
“speech and petitioning, reasonably exercised, in shopping centers even when
the centers are privately owned.”23 Cal.3d 899, 910, 592 P.2d 341, 347 (1979)..
. .
Before this
Court, appellants contend that their constitutionally established rights under
the Fourteenth
Amendment to exclude appellees from adverse use of appellants’
private property cannot be denied by invocation of a state constitutional
provision or by judicial reconstruction of a State’s laws of private property.
We postponed consideration of the question of jurisdiction until the hearing of
the case on the merits. 444
U.S. 949.
We now affirm.
II
We initially
conclude that this case is properly before us as an appeal under 28
U.S.C. § 1257(2). . . .
III
Appellants
first contend that Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner,407 U.S. 551 (1972),
prevents the State from requiring a private shopping center owner to provide
access to persons exercising their state constitutional rights of free speech
and petition when adequate alternative avenues of communication are available. Lloyd
dealt with the question whether, under the Federal Constitution, a privately
owned shopping center may prohibit the distribution of handbills on its
property when the handbilling is unrelated to the shopping center’s operations.
Id. at 552. The shopping center had adopted a strict policy against the
distribution of handbills within the building complex and its malls, and it
made no exceptions to this rule. Id. at 555. . . Respondents in Lloyd argued that,
because the shopping center was open to the public, the First
Amendment prevents the private owner from enforcing the handbilling
restriction on shopping center premises. Id. at 564.. . . [p81]
In rejecting this claim, we substantially repudiated the rationale of 407
U.S. 551
(1972), prevents the State from requiring a private shopping center owner to
provide access to persons exercising their state constitutional rights of free
speech and petition when adequate alternative avenues of communication are
available. Lloyd dealt with the question whether, under the Federal
Constitution, a privately owned shopping center may prohibit the distribution
of handbills on its property when the handbilling is unrelated to the shopping
center’s operations. Id. at 552. The shopping center had adopted a
strict policy against the distribution of handbills within the building complex
and its malls, and it made no exceptions to this rule. Id. at 555.. .
. Respondents in Lloyd argued that, because the shopping center was
open to the public, the First Amendment prevents the private owner from
enforcing the handbilling restriction on shopping center premises. Id.
at 564.. . . [p81] In rejecting this claim, we
substantially repudiated the rationale of Food Employees v. Logan Valley
Plaza,391 U.S. 308]391
U.S. 308
(198), which was later overruled in 391 U.S. 308 (198), which was later
overruled in Hudgens v. NLRB,424
U.S. 507
(1976). We stated that property does not lose its private character merely
because the public is generally invite to use it for designated purposes,” and
that “ [t]he essentially private character of a store and its privately owned
abutting property does not change by virtue of being large or clustered with
other stores in a modern shopping center.”407 U.S. at 569.
Our reasoning
in Lloyd, however, does not, ex propriovigore, limit the
authority of the State to exercise its police power or its sovereign right to
adopt in its own Constitution individual liberties more expansive than those
conferred by the Federal Constitution. Cooper v. California,386
U.S. 58,
62 (1967). See also 407 U.S. at 569-570. In Lloyd, supra, there
was no state constitutional or statutory provision that had been construed to
create rights to the use of private property by strangers, comparable to those
found to exist by the California Supreme Court here. It is, of course, well
established that a State, in the exercise of its police power, may adopt
reasonable restrictions on private property so long as the restrictions do not
amount to a taking without just compensation or contravene any other federal
constitutional provision. See, e.g., Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co.,272
U.S. 365 (1926); Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc.,427 U.S.
50 (1976).Lloyd held that, when a shopping center owner opens his
private property to the public for the purpose of shopping, the First
Amendment to the United States Constitution does not thereby create
individual rights in expression beyond those already existing under applicable
law. See also Hudgens v. NLRB, supra at 517-521. [p82]
IV
Appellants next
contend that a right to exclude others underlies the Fifth Amendment
guarantee against the taking of property without just compensation and the Fourteenth
Amendment guarantee against the deprivation of property without due process
of law. . . .
Here the
requirement that appellants permit appellees to exercise state-protected rights
of free expression and petition on shopping center property clearly does not
amount to an unconstitutional infringement of appellants’ property right under
the Taking Clause. There is nothing to suggest that preventing appellants from
prohibiting this sort of activity will unreasonably impair the value or use of
their property as a shopping center. . .
.
There is also
little merit to appellants’ argument that they have been denied their property
without due process of law. . . .
V
Appellants
finally contend that a private property owner has a First Amendment
right not to be forced by the State to use his property as a forum for the
speech of others.. . . They
[p86] state that, in Wooley v. Maynard,430
U.S. 705
(1977), this Court concluded that a State may not constitutionally require an
individual to participate in the dissemination of an ideological [p87]
message by displaying it on his private property in a manner and for the
express purpose that it be observed and read by the public. This rationale
applies here, they argue, because the message of Wooley is that the
State may not force an individual to display any message at all.
Wooley, however, was a
case in which the government itself prescribed the message, required it to be
displayed openly on appellee’s personal property that was used “as part of his
daily life,” and refused to permit him to take any measures to cover up the
motto even though the Court found that the display of the motto served no
important state interest. Here, by contrast, there are a number of
distinguishing factors. Most important, the shopping center, by choice of its
owner, is not limited to the personal use of appellants. It is instead a
business establishment that is open to the public to come and go as they
please. The views expressed by members of the public in passing out pamphlets
or seeking signatures for a petition thus will not likely be identified with
those of the owner. Second, no specific message is dictated by the State to be
displayed on appellants’ property. There consequently is no danger of
governmental discrimination for or against a particular message. Finally, as
far as appears here, appellants can expressly disavow any connection with the
message by simply posting signs in the area where the speakers or handbillers
stand. Such signs, for example, could disclaim any sponsorship of the message
and could explain that the persons are communicating their own messages by
virtue of state law.
. .
.
We conclude
that neither appellants’ federally recognized property rights nor their First
Amendment right have been infringed by the California Supreme Court’s
decision recognizing a right of appellees to exercise state-protected rights of
expression and petition on appellants’ property. The judgment of the Supreme
Court of California is therefore
Affirmed.
MR. JUSTICE
BLACKMUN joins the opinion of the Court except that sentence thereof, ante
at 84, which reads:
Nor [p89]
as a general proposition is the United States, as opposed to the several
States, possessed of residual authority that enables it to define “property” in
the first instance.
__________
III. Hierarchies of Law within the Domestic
Legal Order and Between National and International Law Reflecting Governmental
Order
Over the course of the last several
classes the student has been introduced to the relationship between the state,
its government and systems of law as it has developed in the West. We started
with an exploration of the premises of most important approaches to the
construction of relationships between law, the state and a government. Beyond
the substantive characteristics of each, and their similarities and differences,
the student was also introduced to the effects of each set of ordering premises
on the fundamental relationship between the individual, the political community
and their government. On an as applied basis, it provides the student with the
tools that make an understanding of different political systems, and their
relationship to law, more understandable. In addition, the student was also
exposed to the way in which each of these approaches communicate. Ultimately
the object was to provide students with the outlines of the framework within
which the modern law-state has been created and deployed in domestic and global
governance.
The class then turned to the issue
of ordering law within each of these framing structures. In the face of the
structuring characteristics of the modern law-state, how do states order law,
and by ordering law, implement theoretical premises about the relationship of
the individual to government and government to law. The focus of the class was
on two principal objectives. The first was to explore the creation and the
legitimacy of “higher law” that both constrains the state and its government,
which has become the basis of modern constitutional law. The second was to
explore a consequence of this establishment of a “higher law” system for
ordering government, and its effects for ordering “inferior” law that may
otherwise be declared or enacted by courts, legislatures or administrative
bodies. Together these two facets of law-ordering creates what is commonly
understood as the domestic legal order of a state. That is, the domestic legal
order of a state refers both to the ordering of law within a state and also to
the mechanics by which government is constituted, constrained, and legitimated
by a states “higher law” and by which a government contributes to the
enactment, implementation and enforcement of law.
The management of legal hierarchies
in the United States was then introduced.
The doctrine of preemption serves as the tool through which
multi-jurisdictional states—federal states like the United States, and
federative unions of states, like the European Union—manage the multi-system
legal orders. The object is coherence
within a governance space in which law operates through multiple autonomous but
related sub systems (common law, statutes, etc.) organized in simple
hierarchies (recall the Indiana statute on legal hierarchy) within states, and
in more complex relationships between state hierarchically ordered law systems
and those of a superior governmental system (the United States general
government), which share authority over the subject of legal regulation. The system of preemption is made complicated
precisely because multi-level federations now legislate in areas traditionally
left to non-state social norm systems, and because of a shift on political
consensus that once favored local law making and now favors law making at the
national level.
In a world in which the state represented the repository of the highest law of the territory within which its authority could be enforced, the domestic legal order of states expressed both a description of a system of law-states, and also gave expression to the premise that the law-state was the highest form of legitimate law making. Beyond that was the world of the “law of nations” in a modern version not far different from its conception at the time of the Institutes (e.g., Emer de Vattel, Le Droit des Gens[4] (James Brown Scott ed., translation of the 1758 edition by Charles G. Fenwick (another English language version[5])), and from the 19th century a more formalized structure of contract relations between states, managed under a system of treaties and custom understood as international law.[6] These applied as contracts among equals among the family of civilized nations but could be used to support colonization or the making of unequal treaties when superior nations engaged in state to state relations with an inferior state. Before 1945, this system, of international law produced a bifurcated approach to law systems. On the one hand the system of law produced within a state, the sum of which constituted its domestic legal order, was understood to apply directly to individuals and understood as the legitimate expression of popular sovereignty because it proceeded from the people or their representatives in ways sanctioned by the “higher (constitutional) law” of the state. On the other hand, the obligations incurred by states among each other were said to bind states, as juridical entities, but had no effect within the territory of a state unless, under the rules provided for this purpose within a state, these treaty or customary obligations, were incorporated into the domestic legal order of a state. In the absence of that incorporation there was no automatic transposition of international into domestic law and individuals within a state had neither rights nor obligations under these provisions, however much they might want either.
But especially since the middle of the 20th century, law and law systems have once again become more detached from the state, and assumed an autonomy that might produce a direct connection between international law and individuals wherever situated irrespective of the action or inaction of an intermediary state. This change is described in your reading, Larry Catá Backer, Inter-Systemic Harmonization and Its Challenges for the Legal-State,[7] in FICHL Publication Series No. 11 (2011): The Law of the Future and the Future of the Law 427-437 (Editors: Sam Muller, Stavros Zouridis, Morly Frishman and Laura Kistemaker; Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Oslo, 2011). Again, the object is coherence, but the vantage point has changed. Were the state once stood at the apex of legal regulation, now it is increasingly subsumed within higher order systems, both public (international state based institutions) and private. Harmonization is currently proceeding along different lines that reflect ambiguous and multi-vector interactions between traditional and emerging governance actors and that suggest the context in which the future of legal systems, however understood, will be determined. This think piece first considers the foundations. The great 19th century project of horizontal harmonization, centered on states and their domestic law systems. The 20th century project of vertical harmonization focused on legal internationalization, from which the edifices of supra-national institutions and public transnational law evolve. It then turns to the current challenge of inter-systemic harmonization. Founded on governance polycentricity, of the mechanics of law beyond the domestic legal orders of states, of the rise of private law with public functions, and of public entities as private actors, it is changing the landscape of law. The greatest challenge for law is to avoid becoming irrelevant where corporations use contracts to govern their supply chains, states become private market actors, and private enterprises regulate markets by assessment and rating.
The development of supra-national
norm making, at first centered on the United Nations and its related
organizations, and then spreading to a number of the multilateral public
organizations, have created a system of norm and law making that seeks to
regulate areas of conduct once reserved to states. More importantly, these
international organizations not only began producing regulation and law but
also began to understand their governance role as inter connected with the law
of the domestic legal orders of the member states of these organizations.
(e.g., José E. Alvarez, International Organizations as Law-Makers,
Oxford University Press, 2006). Globalization also tended to shift regulatory
emphasis from states to a “transnational” space beyond, though not clearly
vertically arranged against the domestic legal orders of states with which they
came in contact. (e.g., Gunther Teubner,‘Global Bukowina’[8]: Legal Pluralism
in the World Society,[9]in Global
Law Without a State 3-28 (Gunther Teubner ed., 1997)). Some states
created mechanisms for the automatic incorporation of their international law
obligations within their domestic legal orders. Others placed international law
obligations within the hierarchy of their laws, sometimes placing international
law above and sometimes on the same level as domestic statutes. Still others
retained a high wall between the international obligations of the state and its
domestic legal order, requiring a positive transposition of international law
by legislative action or by the inclusion in the treaty itself of an explicit
provision for automatic incorporation upon approval of the treaty by the
legislature. In any case, the relation of the international obligations of
states to other aspects of law has always been treated, and especially so in
the United States, as something apart from domestic legislation. Complicating
the situation was the rise of international organizations with authority to
create international rules or set standards with sometimes binding effects.
Lastly, some aspects of both international treaty law and custom have come to
be accepted by many, if not most states as binding whether or not a state
consents to their application. These peremptory norms, jus cogens,[10] remain quite
controversial (e.g., Inter-American Court, The Legal Status and Rights of
Undocumented Migrants, Mexico,[11] Advisory Opinion OC-18/03
(Decision No) Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (Ser. A) No. 18 (Official Case No)IHRL 3237
(IACHR 2003), issued September 17, 2003).
For today’s class students will consider these issues as applied in the United States. We will use as the basis of our examination the discussion in Medellín v. Texas,[12] 128 S.Ct. 1346 (2008). The case presents a useful example of the way in which state, federal and national governments, and their legal orders, now intersect within the law-state system of the United States. Its complexity provides a window on the realities of the application of law where multiple jurisdictions and systems of law may apply simultaneously to a single event or series of events.
The facts of the case are fairly straightforward:
Petitioner Jose
Ernesto Medellin, a Mexican national, has lived in the United States since
preschool. A member of the “Black and Whites” gang, Medellin was convicted of
capital murder and sentenced to death in Texas for the gang rape and brutal
murders of two Houston teenagers.
.
. . .
Medellin was arrested at approximately 4 a.m. on June 29, 1993. A few hours later, between 5:54 and 7:23 a.m., Medellin was given Miranda warnings; he then signed a written waiver and gave a detailed written confession. App. to Brief for Respondent 32-36. Local law enforcement officers did not, however, inform Medellin of his Vienna Convention right to notify the Mexican consulate of his detention. Brief for Petitioner 6-7. Medellin was convicted of capital murder and sentenced to death; his conviction and sentence were affirmed on appeal. Medellin v. State, No. 71,997 (Tex. Crim. App., May 16, 1997), App. to Brief for Respondent 2-31.
But because
Medellin was a Mexican national, the interests of Mexico in the welfare of its
citizens and as memorialized in agreements between the United States and Mexico
might also play a part. In 1969, the United States ratified the Vienna
Convention on Consular Relations[13] and the Optional Protocol
Concerning the Compulsory Settlement of Disputes to the Vienna Convention[14] (Optional Protocol or
Protocol) on Apr. 24, 1963. The preamble to the Convention sets out as one of
its purposes to “contribute to the development of friendly relations among
nations.” 21 U.S.T., at 79. Consequently, Convention Article 36, to “facilitat[e]
the exercise of consular functions” (Art. 36(1), 21 U.S.T., at 100), provides
that if a person detained by a foreign country “so requests, the competent
authorities of the receiving State shall, without delay, inform the consular
post of the sending State” of such detention, and “inform the [detainee] of his
righ[t]” to request assistance from the consul of his own state. Art. 36(1)(b),
id., at 101. Disputes arising out of an interpretation of the Convention are to
be resolved in the International Court of Justice[15] under its compulsory
jurisdiction. U.N. member states undertake to comply with ICJ decisions.
The United
States originally consented to the general jurisdiction of the ICJ when it
filed a declaration recognizing compulsory jurisdiction under Art. 36(2) in
1946. The United States withdrew from general ICJ jurisdiction in 1985. See U.
S. Dept. of State Letter and Statement Concerning Termination of Acceptance of
ICJ Compulsory Jurisdiction (Oct. 7, 1985), reprinted in 24 I. L. M. 1742
(1985). By ratifying the Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention, the United
States consented to the specific jurisdiction of the ICJ with respect to claims
arising out of the Vienna Convention. On March 7, 2005, subsequent to the ICJ’s
judgment in Avena, the United States gave notice of withdrawal from the
Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention. Letter from Condoleezza Rice,
Secretary of State, to Kofi A. Annan, Secretary-General of the United Nations.
(Medellin, supra ).
No issue of
international law was raised during the course of the arrest, or trial court
proceedings. “Medellin first raised his Vienna Convention claim in his first
application for state post-conviction relief. The state trial court held that
the claim was procedurally defaulted because Medellin had failed to raise it at
trial or on direct review. The trial court also rejected the Vienna Convention
claim on the merits, finding that Medellin had “fail[ed] to show that any
non-notification of the Mexican authorities impacted on the validity of his
conviction or punishment.” Id., at 62. The Texas Court of Criminal Appeals
affirmed.” (Ibid). At this point, Medellin filed a federal habeas corpus[16]petition in the federal
district court. It was denied. While this denial was on appeal to the Fifth
Circuit,
“the ICJ issued
its decision in Avena [and Other Mexican Nationals; Mexico v. United States of
America, 2004 I. C. J. 12[17] (Judgment of Mar. 31).
The ICJ held that the United States had violated Article 36(1)(b) of the Vienna
Convention by failing to inform the 51 named Mexican nationals, including
Medellin, of their Vienna Convention rights. 2004 I. C. J., at 53-55. In the
ICJ’s determination, the United States was obligated “to provide, by means of
its own choosing, review and reconsideration of the convictions and sentences
of the [affected] Mexican nationals.” Id., at 72, P 153(9).. The ICJ indicated
that such review was required without regard to state procedural default rules.
Id., at 56-57.” (Ibid).
The Fifth
Circuit then ruled against Medellin. The U.S. Supreme Court then granted
certiorari,[18]
Medellin v. Dretke, 544 U.S. 660, 661, 125 S. Ct. 2088, 161 L. Ed. 2d 982
(2005) (per curiam) (Medellin I). Before the Supreme Court heard oral argument,
however, then President George W. Bush issued a Memorandum for the United
States Attorney General, which provided:
“I have
determined, pursuant to the authority vested in me as President by the
Constitution and the laws of the United States of America, that the United
States will discharge its international obligations under the decision of the
International Court of Justice in [Avena], by having State courts give effect
to the decision in accordance with general principles of comity in cases filed
by the 51 Mexican nationals addressed in that decision.” App. to Pet. for Cert.
187a. (Medellin, supra).
Relying on both the Presidential Memorandum and the ICJ Avena decision, Medellin filed a second application for habeas relief in state court. Ex parte Medellin, 223 S. W. 3d 315, 322-323 (Tex. Crim. App. 2006). That appeal was then dismissed by the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals as an abuse of the writ. Ex Parte Medellín, 223 S. W. 3d, 315, at 352 (Tex. Ct. Crim. App. 2006). In that court’s view, neither the Avena decision nor the President’s Memorandum was “binding federal law” that could displace the State’s limitations on the filing of successive habeas applications. Ibid. The U.S. Supreme Court granted certiorari. 550 U.S. 917, 127 S. Ct. 2129, 167 L. Ed. 2d 862 (2007). The U.S. Supreme Court then had two significant issues to deal with―the first was the effect of international law on American jurisprudence and its incorporation into the decisions of American courts. The second was an issue of federalism, touching on the effect of a Presidential Memorandum purportedly issued under the President’s foreign affairs powers on the application and interpretation of the criminal law of a state.
With respect to the first issue, the Supreme Court first summarized its view of the relationship of international law to the domestic law of the United States.
No one disputes
that the Avena decision―a decision that flows from the treaties through
which the United States submitted to ICJ jurisdiction with respect to Vienna
Convention disputes―constitutes an international law obligation on the part of
the United States. But not all international law obligations automatically
constitute binding federal law enforceable in United States courts. The
question we confront here is whether the Avena judgment has automatic
domestic legal effect such that the judgment of its own force applies in state
and federal courts.
This Court has long recognized the distinction between treaties that automatically have effect as domestic law, and those that―while they constitute international law commitments―do not by themselves function as binding federal law. The distinction was well explained by Chief Justice Marshall’s opinion in Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet. 253, 315, 7 L. Ed. 415 (1829), overruled on other grounds, United States v. Percheman, 32 U.S. 51, 7 Pet. 51, 8 L. Ed. 604 (1833), which held that a treaty is “equivalent to an act of the legislature,” and hence self-executing, when it “operates of itself without the aid of any legislative provision.” Foster, supra, at 314, 2 Pet. 253, 315, 7 L. Ed. 415. When, in contrast, “[treaty] stipulations are not self-executing they can only be enforced pursuant to legislation to carry them into effect.” Whitney v. Robertson, 124 U.S. 190, 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed. 386 (1888). In sum, while treaties “may comprise international commitments . . . they are not domestic law unless Congress has either enacted implementing statutes or the treaty itself conveys an intention that it be ‘self-executing’ and is ratified on these terms.” Igartua-De La Rosa v. United States, 417 F.3d 145, 150 (CA1 2005) (en banc) (Boudin, C. J.).
This Court has long recognized the distinction between treaties that automatically have effect as domestic law, and those that―while they constitute international law commitments―do not by themselves function as binding federal law. The distinction was well explained by Chief Justice Marshall’s opinion in Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253, 2 Pet. 253, 315, 7 L. Ed. 415 (1829), overruled on other grounds, United States v. Percheman, 32 U.S. 51, 7 Pet. 51, 8 L. Ed. 604 (1833), which held that a treaty is “equivalent to an act of the legislature,” and hence self-executing, when it “operates of itself without the aid of any legislative provision.” Foster, supra, at 314, 2 Pet. 253, 315, 7 L. Ed. 415. When, in contrast, “[treaty] stipulations are not self-executing they can only be enforced pursuant to legislation to carry them into effect.” Whitney v. Robertson, 124 U.S. 190, 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed. 386 (1888). In sum, while treaties “may comprise international commitments . . . they are not domestic law unless Congress has either enacted implementing statutes or the treaty itself conveys an intention that it be ‘self-executing’ and is ratified on these terms.” Igartua-De La Rosa v. United States, 417 F.3d 145, 150 (CA1 2005) (en banc) (Boudin, C. J.).
A treaty is, of course, “primarily a compact between independent nations.” Head Money Cases, 112 U.S. 580, 598, 5 S. Ct. 247, 28 L. Ed. 798 (1884). It ordinarily “depends for the enforcement of its provisions on the interest and the honor of the governments which are parties to it.” Ibid..... Only “[i]f the treaty contains stipulations which are self-executing, that is, require no legislation to make them operative, [will] they have the force and effect of a legislative enactment.” Whitney, supra, at 194, 8 S. Ct. 456, 31 L. Ed. 386.
So far so good,
but Medellin then suggested that the Avena decision was binding as law within
the United States because the relevant U.N. Charter provisions, the Optional
Protocol and the ICJ Statute were effectively self-executing. A majority of the
justices disagreed.
To arrive at this determination, the Supreme Court described what it considered the appropriate interpretive analysis for cases of this kind. Because statutes are at issue, it interpretation starts with the relevant text (Ibid; Part II.A). But, “‘Because a treaty ratified by the United States is “an agreement among sovereign powers,’ we have also considered as “aids to its interpretation” the negotiation and drafting history of the treaty as well as “the post ratification understanding” of signatory nations. Zicherman v. Korean Air Lines Co., 516 U.S. 217, 226, 116 S. Ct. 629, 133 L. Ed. 2d 596 (1996).” (Ibid). The majority suggested that the “most natural reading of the Optional Protocol is as a bare grant of jurisdiction.” (Ibid). In any case, they reasoned, the obligation to comply with ICJ judgments arises from the U.N. Charter and not the Optional Protocol. But if that is the case, the Court determined, then the operative language, that each member state undertakes to comply with ICJ decisions means only that the member state commits “to take future action through their political branches to comply with an ICJ decision.” Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae in Medellin I, O. T. 2004, No. 04-5928, p 34.” (Ibid). Thus, the undertaking is a political undertaking not a legal one. In effect, the U.N. Charter, the majority suggests, commits the United States only to endeavor to transpose ICJ judgments into domestic law. For this purpose, the Supreme Court relied on both the position of the U.S. government and its application of prior cases, and its inference from the framework for the enforcement of ICJ decisions. “It is, moreover, well settled that the United States’ interpretation of a treaty “is entitled to great weight.” Sumitomo Shoji America, Inc. v. Avagliano, 457 U.S. 176, 184-185, 102 S. Ct. 2374, 72 L. Ed. 2d 765 (1982). . . . The Executive Branch has unfailingly adhered to its view that the relevant treaties do not create domestically enforceable federal law. See Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 4, 27-29.” (Ibid).
In sum,
Medellin’s view that ICJ decisions are automatically enforceable as domestic
law is fatally undermined by the enforcement structure established by Article
94. His construction would eliminate the option of noncompliance contemplated
by Article 94(2), undermining the ability of the political branches to
determine whether and how to comply with an ICJ judgment. Those sensitive
foreign policy decisions would instead be transferred to state and federal
courts charged with applying an ICJ judgment directly as domestic law. And
those courts would not be empowered to decide whether to comply with the
judgment―again, always regarded as an option by the political branches―any more
than courts may consider whether to comply with any other species of domestic
law. This result would be particularly anomalous in light of the principle that
“[t]he conduct of the foreign relations of our Government is committed by the
Constitution to the Executive and Legislative―’the political’―Departments.”
Oetjen v. Central Leather Co., 246 U.S. 297, 302, 38 S. Ct. 309, 62 L. Ed. 726
(1918).
The majority
then faults the dissenting opinion for misreading the texts and misinterpreting
the other sources relied on. The dissent, the majority tells the reader, failed
to appropriately consider the text. “As against this time-honored textual
approach, the dissent proposes a multifactor, judgment-by-judgment analysis
that would “jettiso[n] relative predictability for the open-ended
rough-and-tumble of factors.” Jerome B. Grubart, Inc. v. Great Lakes Dredge
& Dock Co., 513 U.S. 527, 547, 115 S. Ct. 1043, 130 L. Ed. 2d 1024 (1995).”
(Ibid., Part II.B). Lastly, in Part II.C., the majority supported its reading
by considering the understanding of other signatory states after ratification.
(Part II.C.). There is a suggestion of the anti-democratic character of holding
that the ICJ decision is self-executing as well as the suggestion that this
result might interfere with the constitutional prerogatives of the federal
courts. (Ibid).
In sum, while
the ICJ’s judgment in Avena creates an international law obligation on the part
of the United States, it does not of its own force constitute binding federal
law that pre-empts state restrictions on the filing of successive habeas
petitions. As we noted in Sanchez-Llamas, a contrary conclusion would be
extraordinary, given that basic rights guaranteed by our own Constitution do
not have the effect of displacing state procedural rules. See 548 U.S., at 360,
126 S. Ct. 2669, 165 L. Ed. 2d 557. Nothing in the text, background,
negotiating and drafting history, or practice among signatory nations suggests
that the President or Senate intended the improbable result of giving the
judgments of an international tribunal a higher status than that enjoyed by “many
of our most fundamental constitutional protections.” (Ibid. Part II.D.)
But what about
the power of the President to compel the Texas courts to apply the treaty? The
Supreme Court agrees that the interests of the United States that the president
was seeking to advance were compelling. But however compelling, the court
argued, in the absence of a constitutionally sufficient power, the President
could not assert authority (or better put, the State of Texas could refuse to
comply with any purported assertion).
Justice Jackson’s
familiar tripartite scheme provides the accepted framework for evaluating
executive action in this area. First, “[w]hen the President acts pursuant to an
express or implied authorization of Congress, his authority is at its maximum,
for it includes all that he possesses in his own right plus all that Congress
can delegate.” Youngstown, 343 U.S., at 635, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62
Ohio Law Abs. 417 (opinion concurring). Second, “[w]hen the President acts in
absence of either a congressional grant or denial of authority, he can only
rely upon his own independent powers, but there is a zone of twilight in which
he and Congress may have concurrent authority, or in which its distribution is
uncertain.” Id., at 637, 72 S. Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 In
this circumstance, Presidential authority can derive support from “congressional
inertia, indifference or quiescence.” Ibid. Finally, “[w]hen the President
takes measures incompatible with the expressed or implied will of Congress, his
power is at its lowest ebb,” and the Court can sustain his actions “only by
disabling the Congress from acting upon the subject.” Id., at 637-638, 72 S.
Ct. 863, 96 L. Ed. 1153, 62 Ohio Law Abs. 417 (Ibid., Part III.A).
The United
States and Medellin advanced three arguments in support of the President’s
authority: (1) that the relevant treaties give the President the authority to
implement the Avena judgment and that Congress has acquiesced in the exercise
of such authority; (2) that the President exercised an “independent”
international dispute-resolution power wholly apart from the asserted authority
based on the pertinent treaties, and (3) that the President’s Memorandum is a
valid exercise of his power to take care that the laws be faithfully executed.
The majority
rejected the first argument on the ground that “the President has an array of
political and diplomatic means available to enforce international obligations,
but unilaterally converting a non-self-executing treaty into a self-executing
one is not among them. The responsibility for transforming an international
obligation arising from a non-self-executing treaty into domestic law falls to
Congress.” (Ibid., III.B.1). In any event, the Court concluded, Congress never
acquiesced to this sort of assertion of Presidential power. The Court
emphasized that no President has the authority to unilaterally execute a non-self-executing
treaty. (Ibid). The Court also rejected the claim that the president had
sufficient authority under his foreign affairs powers. (Ibid., III.B.2). This
claim depended on Congressional acquiescence, of which the Court found none.
The court rejected the third argument on the grounds that the power to execute
the laws did not include within it the power to enact them. (Ibid., III.B.3).
For those reasons, the State of Texas was free to ignore the Presidential
memorandum as of no legal effect.
Whatever one
thinks of the merits of the majority’s reasoning, the Medellin case thus
provides a very clear picture of the construction of the hierarchy of law in
the United States, and especially the application of international law within
the American domestic legal order. International law that is self-executing when
made has the same effect as statutes passed by Congress. They need not be
enacted anew. On the other hand, they can be repealed, modified or ignored by
subsequent enactments of Congress, even if the language of the treaty itself
committed the United States to refrain from doing any of those things. Unlike
other states, self-executed international law has no special or superior place
within the American hierarchy of law. The same is true of law enacted by
Congress to transpose international obligations into national law. The
techniques of statutorily interpretation will be applied to determine whether a
treaty is self-executed and the focus, in these cases will be on the text of
the treaty and the intent of the executive in negotiating the treaty. The post ratification
behavior of the state parties may also serve as evidence of the intent of the
parties relating to the meaning of the treaty. The President may not compel
states to comply with the treaty obligations that the United States has
ratified, absent legitimately enacted statutes that transpose these state to
state obligations into domestic law. Neither may the President appear to
effectively legislate such compliance in the absence of Congressional acquiesce
or action. Where the Federal Constitution fails to give the President power,
states are free to ignore his command, and state law and practice may prevail
over Presidential desires, even those backed by international commitments to
which the United States (through its federal government) is bound. Thus the
internal and external dimensions of the authority of international law in the
United States and its role in the hierarchy of U.S. law.
It must be remembered, however, that the premises out of which the majority Justices reached their conclusion remain highly contested. That contestation exists on two levels. One level is focused on the peculiarities of U.S. constitutional law. Within the parameters of American constitutional law, the narrow textualism[19]that produced the majority opinion is countered by a functional[20] approach well illustrated by the dissenting Justices. Rather than focusing on the logic of the text at issue and the intent of the drafters in the interpretive construction of the text, the functionalist justice will look to achieving the intent objective of the drafters rather than privileging the textual and formal logic of the text. As the majority in the Medellin case suggested, formalists tend to view the functional approach as veering too close to and sometimes embracing a legislative power that is not for courts to wield. Thus the issue of interpretation, the issue of legal hierarchies and the role of international law in the United States becomes one not merely of the application of law and constitutional principles, but also of the theory of separation of powers (which organ of government has the authority to make these determinations) and of the character of interpretation itself (e.g., when does interpretation become legislation). (Medellin, Part II.B).
The other level
of contestation focuses on the emerging structural framework of international
law and organizations. Internationalists tend to reject the foundational
premises on which the Medellin justices relied. Here the readings may be useful
(Larry Catá Backer, Inter-Systemic Harmonization and Its Challenges for the
Legal-State,[21]
supra). Traditional hierarchies of law, grounded in the ultimate supremacy of
the law-state is sometimes rejected in favor of a legal hierarchy on which at
least conventional international law[22] and jus cogens is
treated as equal or superior to the statutory law of states. This is a set of
presumptions that may be implicitly built into international governance
instruments sometimes (U.N. Guiding Principles of Business and Human Rights).[23] Many states continue to
reject this notion, but internationalists and international public and private
organizations increasingly take the view that international law is both
superior and binding not just on states but also directly on the residents and
juridical persons residing in any state that may be part of the community of
states that have produced this law. One approach is based on the premise that
the community of nations, especially where each is legitimately established
under democratic principles, has the authority to constrict common laws of
nations that ought to be directly applied to all members of that governance
community. But this is countered by those who view this as illegitimate because
of the democratic deficit[24] in its development―that is
that international law is developed and agreed by institutions with no direct
connection with the people in whom sovereignty is vested. In either case, what
is becoming clear is that, while the Medellin opinion represents a very nice
application of the classical theory of legal hierarchy between domestic and
international law, one that still has strong adherents, that classical theory
is in fact under sustained challenge. But that challenge is coming not form the
law-state but form the emerging international community and with respect to the
law/governance structures they are producing.
The final
reading for this class session, PruneYard Shopping Ctr. V. Robins,[25] 447 U. S. 74 (1980),
suggests the limits of federal authority to shape or constrain state law. In
this case the Supreme Court held that a state could interpret its constitution
to prohibit the private owner of a shopping center from using state trespass law
to exclude peaceful expressive activity in the open areas of the shopping
center. The issue turned on the ability of the State of California to impose
constitutional requirements under its own state constitution different form
that sufficient under the Federal Constitution. Thus two principles emerge.
First, under the U.S. Constitution,[26] states[27] can provide their
citizens with broader rights in their constitutions than under the federal
Constitution, so long as those rights do not infringe on any federal
constitutional rights. Second under the constitution of the State of
California, that power extends to the protection of the right to free speech.
For the student concerned with issues of hierarchy another insight emerges―legal
hierarchies in the United States may not be entirely rigid, and indeed may be
porous in certain respects. Thus while in this case federal constitutional law
could constrain the scope of California’s constitution, where the state sought
to act in a way that was different from but not in opposition to the federal
constitutional principle, that action might not be deemed impermissible. But
the arbiter of this porosity is the court.
PruneYard reminds us again, of course, of the importance of hierarchy in law. In that case, state constitutional law, which is supreme within the domestic legal order of a state, must itself conform to the superior effects of the constitution of the community of states to which California is a member. It is thus against the overriding constraints of federal constitutional (and to some extent statutory) law, that the California constitution must be read. PruneYard also provides an insight into the arguments rejected in Medellin. There the plurality rejected the application of a similar relationship between international law and the constitutional law of the United States. They rejected the idea of a hierarchy in which international law sat atop the constitutional and domestic legal order of states in favor of a view that treated the two systems as distinct through connected through the intermediation of consent in which legislatures evidenced acquiescence through legal transposition (the enactment of international obligation into domestic law through statutes and the like).
Yet it is also important to remember that there is a hierarchy of international law, one that in some ways is as contested that that within domestic legal orders (Larry Catá Backer, Sovereign Investing and Markets-Based Transnational Legislative Power: The Norwegian Sovereign Wealth Fund in Global Markets,[28] 29 American University International Law Review – (forthcoming 2013)). Sometimes the hierarchy is explicitly bound up with the issues of the appropriate sources of law to be applied by international bodies. The Statute of the International Court of Justice,[29] which played a prominent role in Medellin, for example, provides:
1. The Court,
whose function is to decide in accordance with international law such disputes
as are submitted to it, shall apply:
a.
international conventions, whether general or particular, establishing rules
expressly recognized by the contesting states;
b.
international custom, as evidence of a general practice accepted as law;
c.
the general principles of law recognized by civilized nations;
d.
subject to the provisions of article 59, judicial decisions and the teachings
of the most highly qualified publicists of the various nations , as subsidiary
means for the determination of rules of law.
2. This
provision shall not prejudice the power of the Court to decide a case ex
aequo et bono,[30] if the parties agree
thereto. (Statute ¶ 38).
This suggests
both the scope of international law that is generally and conventionally
recognized by public international law and also the hierarchy within which they
are woven together for purposes of application and interpretation. It also
suggests that, like the law of the United States, international law recognizes
both a customary element as well as a private element, the latter of which
might invoke equity. More interesting still, and reflecting practices in civil
law countries, international law sometimes permits the persuasive use of
academic writing as well as the reasoned opinions of other courts, that is of
courts whose decisions do not otherwise bind.
A harder
question for international law is the extent to which “soft law” fits into the
hierarchy of international law. Soft laware instruments that may be produced by
international public organizations but that do not have the binding effect of
either domestic or international law. Traditionally these were viewed as
aspirational with no binding effect. But sometimes their provisions become so
well accepted that they become part of customary law and to some extent
binding, or are otherwise taken up and incorporated into traditional
international law instruments. They are thus seen as valuable as transitional
instruments. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights[31] is a good example. (e.g.,
Roberto Andorno, “The Invaluable Role of Soft Law in the Development of
Universal Norms in Bioethics”,[32] paper at a Workshop
jointly organized by the German Ministry of Foreign Affairs and the German
UNESCO Commission, Berlin, 15 February 2007). Some soft law instruments, such
as the Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises[33] of the Organization for Economic
Cooperation and Development[34] provide more complex
examples of soft law. Here soft law contains not just a set of substantive
standards that, though not binding, are require OECD Member States to provide
mechanisms through which parties may seek to complain of violations of the Guidelines.
(Backer, Larry Catá, Rights and Accountability in Development (Raid) V Das Air
and Global Witness V Afrimex: Small Steps Toward an Autonomous Transnational
Legal System for the Regulation of Multinational Corporations,[35] Melbourne Journal of
International Law, Vol. 10, 2010). Lastly private codes of conduct are the most
problematic governance instrument within conventional international law. Many
traditionalists don’t consider them either soft or law―at most private contract
or quasi contract among its parties. (considered in Jan Klabbers, Reflections
on Soft International Law in a Privatized World[36]) Others view these as the
elements of emerging systems of transnational governance. (Gunther Teubner,
Global Bukowina: Legal Pluralism in the World Society,[37] Gunther Teubner (ed.),
Global Law Without a State (Dartmouth, Aldershot 1997, 3-28 Backer, Larry Catá,
Multinational Corporations as Objects and Sources of Transnational Regulation.[38] ILSA Journal of
International & Comparative Law, Vol. 14, No. 2, 2008).
IV. Problem.
The
object of the problem that follows is to provide the student with an
opportunity to synthesize the materials presented and to apply it in a slightly
different context. The object for the
student is to think through the ramifications both of the way in which legal
hierarchies are ordered and the constraining principles that serve to mediate
their application.
Problem:
Assume
the following facts: You are a member of the Attorney General’s office of the
State of New Mexico. New Mexico has extensively regulated the sale of liquor
within its borders. Among other
statutes, New Mexico law provides that beer and wine may not be sold in the
same store. In addition, New Mexico
limits sale of liquor other than beer and wine to persons who can demonstrate
that they are older than 26 years of age.
However, liquor may be sold bi licensed establishments any day of the
week between the hours of 9 AM and 7 PM.
The
United States and Mexico have been concerned about liquor fueled crime in the
border area. They are particularly
concerned in places around El Paso Texas and Juarez Mexico. The governments of both nations determine that
a comprehensive approach is in order and enter into the U.S. Mexico Liquor
Control Treaty. Among its provisions are
the following: (1) no establishment may sell liquor from Friday evening at 8 PM
through Sunday noon if located on an interstate highway (U.S.) or national road
(Mexico) within 100 miles of the border, or in any case within thirty (30)
miles of the border; and (2) any person with a valid proof of age may purchase
beer wine and other liquor in either country upon proof of age of 21 or older.
The Treaty entered into force in January
and in the same month Congress enacted and the President signed a bill that
enacted all of the Treaty’s provisions into law.
The
new Mexico Governor is furious and she directs the Attorney General to determine
whether the President and Congress have the authority to effectively void New
Mexico liquor law. Write a short memo
analyzing the issue and stating your conclusion. The following materials may
provide you with some guidance in addition to the materials read earlier in the
chapter.
State of Missouri v. Holland
252 U.S. 416
(1920)
MR. JUSTICE
HOLMES delivered the opinion of the court.
This is a bill
in equity brought by the State of Missouri to prevent a game warden of the
United States from attempting to enforce the Migratory Bird Treaty Act of
[p431] July 3, 1918, c. 128, 40 Stat. 755, and the regulations made by the
Secretary of Agriculture in pursuance of the same. The ground of the bill is
that the statute is an unconstitutional interference with the rights reserved
to the States by the Tenth Amendment, and that the acts of the defendant done
and threatened under that authority invade the sovereign right of the State and
contravene its will manifested in statutes. The State also alleges a pecuniary
interest, as owner of the wild birds within its borders and otherwise, admitted
by the Government to be sufficient, but it is enough that the bill is a
reasonable and proper means to assert the alleged quasi sovereign rights of a
State. Kansas v. Colorado, 185 U.S. 125, 142. Georgia v. Tennessee Copper Co.,
206 U.S. 230, 237. Marshall Dental Manufacturing Co. v. Iowa, 226 U.S. 460,
462. A motion to dismiss was sustained by the District Court on the ground that
the act of Congress is constitutional. 258 Fed. Rep. 479. Acc., United States
v. Thompson, 258 Fed. Rep. 257; United States v. Rockefeller, 260 Fed.Rep. 346.
The State appeals.
On December 8,
1916, a treaty between the United States and Great Britain was proclaimed by
the President. It recited that many species of birds in their annual migrations
traversed certain parts of the United States and of Canada, that they were of
great value as a source of food and in destroying insects injurious to
vegetation, but were in danger of extermination through lack of adequate
protection. It therefore provided for specified close seasons and protection in
other forms, and agreed that the two powers would take or propose to their
lawmaking bodies the necessary measures for carrying the treaty out. 39 Stat.
1702. The above mentioned Act of July 3, 1918, entitled an act to give effect
to the convention, prohibited the killing, capturing or selling any of the
migratory birds included in the terms of the treaty except as permitted by
regulations compatible with those terms, to be made by [p432] the Secretary of
Agriculture. Regulations were proclaimed on July 31, and October 25, 1918. 40
Stat. 1812; 1863. It is unnecessary to go into any details because, as we have
said, the question raised is the general one whether the treaty and statute are
void as an interference with the rights reserved to the States.
To answer this
question, it is not enough to refer to the Tenth Amendment, reserving the
powers not delegated to the United States, because, by Article II, § 2, the
power to make treaties is delegated expressly, and by Article VI treaties made
under the authority of the United States, along with the Constitution and laws
of the United States made in pursuance thereof, are declared the supreme law of
the land. If the treaty is valid, there can be no dispute about the validity of
the statute under Article I, § 8, as a necessary and proper means to execute the
powers of the Government. The language of the Constitution as to the supremacy
of treaties being general, the question before us is narrowed to an inquiry
into the ground upon which the present supposed exception is placed.
It is said that
a treaty cannot be valid if it infringes the Constitution, that there are
limits, therefore, to the treaty-making power, and that one such limit is that
what an act of Congress could not do unaided, in derogation of the powers
reserved to the States, a treaty cannot do. An earlier act of Congress that
attempted by itself and not in pursuance of a treaty to regulate the killing of
migratory birds within the States had been held bad in the District Court.
United States v. Shauver, 214 Fed.Rep. 154. United States v. McCullagh, 221
Fed.Rep. 288. Those decisions were supported by arguments that migratory birds
were owned by the States in their sovereign capacity for the benefit of their
people, and that, under cases like Geer v. Connecticut, 161 U.S. 519, this
control was one that Congress had no power to displace. The same argument is
supposed to apply now with equal force. [p433]
Whether the two
cases cited were decided rightly or not, they cannot be accepted as a test of
the treaty power. Acts of Congress are the supreme law of the land only when
made in pursuance of the Constitution, while treaties are declared to be so
when made under the authority of the United States. It is open to question
whether the authority of the United States means more than the formal acts prescribed
to make the convention. We do not mean to imply that there are no
qualifications to the treaty-making power, but they must be ascertained in a
different way. It is obvious that there may be matters of the sharpest exigency
for the national wellbeing that an act of Congress could not deal with, but
that a treaty followed by such an act could, and it is not lightly to be
assumed that, in matters requiring national action, "a power which must
belong to and somewhere reside in every civilized government" is not to be
found. Andrews v Andrews, 188 U.S. 14, 33. What was said in that case with
regard to the powers of the States applies with equal force to the powers of
the nation in cases where the States individually are incompetent to act. We
are not yet discussing the particular case before us, but only are considering
the validity of the test proposed. With regard to that we may add that, when we
are dealing with words that also are a constituent act, like the Constitution
of the United States, we must realize that they have called into life a being
the development of which could not have been foreseen completely by the most
gifted of its begetters. It was enough for them to realize or to hope that they
had created an organism; it has taken a century and has cost their successors
much sweat and blood to prove that they created a nation. The case before us
must be considered in the light of our whole experience, and not merely in that
of what was said a hundred years ago. The treaty in question does not contravene
any prohibitory words to be found in the Constitution. The only question is
whether [p434] it is forbidden by some invisible radiation from the general
terms of the Tenth Amendment. We must consider what this country has become in
deciding what that Amendment has reserved.
The State, as
we have intimated, founds its claim of exclusive authority upon an assertion of
title to migratory birds, an assertion that is embodied in statute. No doubt it
is true that, as between a State and its inhabitants, the State may regulate
the killing and sale of such birds, but it does not follow that its authority
is exclusive of paramount powers. To put the claim of the State upon title is
to lean upon a slender reed. Wild birds are not in the possession of anyone, and
possession is the beginning of ownership. The whole foundation of the State's
rights is the presence within their jurisdiction of birds that yesterday had
not arrived, tomorrow may be in another State, and, in a week, a thousand miles
away. If we are to be accurate, we cannot put the case of the State upon higher
ground than that the treaty deals with creatures that, for the moment are
within the state borders, that it must be carried out by officers of the United
States within the same territory, and that, but for the treaty, the State would
be free to regulate this subject itself.
As most of the
laws of the United States are carried out within the States and as many of them
deal with matters which, in the silence of such laws, the State might regulate,
such general grounds are not enough to support Missouri's claim. Valid
treaties, of course, "are as binding within the territorial limits of the
States as they are elsewhere throughout the dominion of the United
States." Baldwin v. Franks, 120 U.S. 678, 683. No doubt the great body of
private relations usually fall within the control of the State, but a treaty
may override its power. We do not have to invoke the later developments of
constitutional law for this proposition; it was recognized as early as Hopkirk
v. Bell, 3 Cranch 454, with regard to statutes [p435] of limitation, and even
earlier, as to confiscation, in Ware v. Hylton, 3 Dall.199. It was assumed by
Chief Justice Marshall with regard to the escheat of land to the State in
Chirac v. Chirac, 2 Wheat. 259, 275. Haguenstein v. Lynham, 100 U.S. 483.
Geofroy v. Riggs, 133 U.S. 258. Blythe v. Hinckley, 180 U.S. 333, 340. So as to
a limited jurisdiction of foreign consuls within a State. Wildenhus' Case, 120
U.S. 1. See Ross v. McIntyre, 140 U.S. 453. Further illustration seems
unnecessary, and it only remains to consider the application of established
rules to the present case.
Here, a
national interest of very nearly the first magnitude is involved. It can be
protected only by national action in concert with that of another power. The
subject matter is only transitorily within the State, and has no permanent
habitat therein. But for the treaty and the statute, there soon might be no
birds for any powers to deal with. We see nothing in the Constitution that
compels the Government to sit by while a food supply is cut off and the
protectors of our forests and our crops are destroyed. It is not sufficient to
rely upon the States. The reliance is vain, and were it otherwise, the question
is whether the United States is forbidden to act. We are of opinion that the
treaty and statute must be upheld. Carey v. South Dakota, 250 U.S. 118.
Decree
affirmed.
Notes and
Questions.
1. What result if the President entered into a
Treaty ratified by the Senate in which the United States agreed to purchase
property from another state; would the ratification of the Treaty serve also to
compel Congress to appropriate the funds necessary to meet this Treaty
obligation? Consider that the federal
Constitution specifically vests the legislative power in Congress and that
appropriation measures must commence in the House of Representatives.
2. The regulation of liquor has a long and
contentious history in the United States.
After a long campaign, the federal Constitution had been amended to
prohibit sales and consumption of most liquor in the early part of the 20th
century. The 18th Amendment (1919)
provided in relevant part that “After one year from the ratification of this
article the manufacture, sale, or transportation of intoxicating liquors
within, the importation thereof into, or the exportation thereof from the
United States and all territory subject to the jurisdiction thereof for
beverage purposes is hereby prohibited.” After a tumultuous decade or so that
constitutional amendment was repealed. Section 2 of the 21st Amendment (1933)
provided that “The transportation or importation into any state, territory, or
possession of the United States for delivery or use therein of intoxicating
liquors, in violation of the laws thereof, is hereby prohibited.”
3. The effect of the 21st Amendment
was to confer regulatory authority on states with respect to liquor. In a series of decisions the Supreme Court
held that power to be quite broad, even when it resulted in the erection of
barriers to trade that would otherwise be prohibited. See, e.g., tate Board of Equalization v.
Young’s Market Co., 299 U.S. 59 (1936) (California licensing fee for
importation); Seagram & Sons v. Hostetter, 384 U.S. 35 (upholding state law
regulating liquor pricing). However, the Supreme Court has refused to validate
state laws that appear to interfere with commerce. In Brown-Forman Distillers Corp. v. New York
State Liquor Authority, 476 U.S. 573 (1986), the Supreme Court invalidated a
state law prohibiting wholesalers form charging lower prices for out of state
sales than those permitted for in state sales under state law.
4. In Granholm v. Heald, 544 U.S. 460 (2005), the
Supreme Court appeared to narrow the scope of state freedom to regulate liquor
sales that have a discriminatory effect on commerce, appearing to substantially
narrow the rule of Young’s Market. The
Court held that the 21st Amendment does not supersede other
provisions of the Constitution, especially those that prohibit state regulation
that inhibits interstate commerce. It
concluded that state liquor laws are valid even when they have a discriminatory
effect State's regime "advances a legitimate local purpose that cannot be
adequately served by reasonable nondiscriminatory alternatives," (citing New
Energy Co. of Ind. v. Limbach, 486 U. S. 269, 278 (1988)).
__________
[1]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1789190
[2]http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct/html/06-984.ZS.html
[3]http://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/447/74/case.html
[4]http://books.google.com/books?id=DeyiAAAAMAAJ&pg=PR30&dq=Le+droit+des+gens++Library+Company+of+Philadelphia&hl=en&ei=SHK4TanFFoXEgAfemuBm&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=1&ved=0CCkQ6AEwAA#v=onepage&q&f=false
[5]
http://www.constitution.org/vattel/vattel_01.htm
[6]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/International_law
[7]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1789190
[8]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=896478
[9]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=896478
[10]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Peremptory_norm
[11]
http://www1.umn.edu/humanrts/iachr/series_A_OC-18.html
[12]
http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct/html/06-984.ZS.html
[13]http://legal.un.org/ilc/texts/instruments/english/conventions/9_2_1963.pdf
[14]http://legal.un.org/ilc/texts/instruments/english/conventions/9_2_1963_disputes.pdf
[15] http://www.icj-cij.org/homepage/
[16]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Habeas_corpus
[17]
http://www.worldcourts.com/icj/eng/decisions/2004.03.31_avena.htm
[18] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Certiorari
[19] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Textualism
[20] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Textualism
[21]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1789190
[22]
http://www.brooklynpeace.org/brooklynforpeace/committees/international-law/fact-sheet-downloads/conventional-and-customary-international-law.pdf
[23]
http://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Publications/GuidingPrinciplesBusinessHR_EN.pdf
[24]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Democratic_deficit_in_the_European_Union
[25] http://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/447/74/case.html
[26]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/U.S._Constitution
[27] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/U.S._state
[28]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2177778
[29]
http://www.icj-cij.org/documents/index.php?p1=4&p2=2&p3=0
[30]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ex_aequo_et_bono
[31]
http://www.ohchr.org/en/udhr/pages/introduction.aspx
[32] http://www.unesco.de/1507.html
[33]http://www.oecd.org/corporate/mne/1922428.pdf
[34] http://www.oecd.org/
[35] http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1427883
[36]
http://www.helsinki.fi/eci/Publications/Klabbers/JKSoft_law_and_public.pdf
[37]
http://www.jura.uni-frankfurt.de/42852872/Bukowina_english.pdf
[38]
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1092167
No comments:
Post a Comment