Pix credit here |
Poul Kjaer, Professor of Governance and Sociology of Law at the Department of
Business Humanities and Law, Copenhagen Business School where he directs
the ERC Advanced Grant Project ‘Global Value Chain Law: Constituting
Connectivity, Contracts and Corporations (GLOBALVALUE)’, has, in the course of work on that project produced a quite interesting forward essay that is itself worth considering. The essay, "What Comes After Critique," was first published on the blog, Transformative Private Law Blog on 16 December 2024.
Pix credit here |
Pix credit here |
But deconstruction, as a form of critique, was also fair game. All of this merged into what now passes for identity grounded critique--one which has taken up the old Frankfurt school economic and sociological critique and rearranged it so that the starting point is not class, but identity--however defined. And that identity politics critique produced its own right wing (mostly) so-called "identitarian" counter critique (on the difference between so-called identity based ideologies and so-called identotarianism see eg here) that like identity based deconstruction has definitive orthodox political objectives. In the process, as is usual for late stage dialectics of critique, the fundamental basis of the order on which critique is itself is founded flounders. Today we live in an age of structural critique in which the glory road to authority--within the life worlds of critique--is grounded in an allegiance to the animating premise that the entirety of social relations (its politics, sociology, morals, law etc.) are built on fatally flawed systems which must themselves be swept away. It is in this sense, perhaps, that one can better appreciate Kjear's insight:
"One reason for the fading away of ‘critique’ is that conceptually more refined and epistemologically more powerful theoretical alternatives are out there now. That does, however, not seem to be the main reason. Rather large parts of the scholarly space and public imagination have fallen prey to group logic and identity thinking representing the antithesis to Kant’s insights and that irrespective of whether it comes in a left- or rightwing version. ("What Comes After Critique, supra)
And yet it may be as important to recall that deconstruction is only one half of the dialectic that makes critique possible. It exists as a reflection, and is animated by and through, acts of construction. It is to that which has been constructed that deconstruction (critique is the polite form of the description) derives its power and place. Critique, indeed, depends as much on the solidity of the object of its critique as it does on the substance of the critique itself. Indeed, the dialectical nature of construction-deconstruction through the habitus of critique that appears to be the central element of both liberal democratic and Marxist-Leninist systems. So now we continue this great phenomenological theater which might better be titled "Perfection as a Moving Target" (for my view from within the lebenwelt of American jurisprudence: The mechanics of perfection : Philosophy, theology, and the foundations of american law; also see the essay in Recovery Review, Let’s Talk About Critique). That remains the essence of this age of the "great sweep" forward. And thus the habitus, perhaps well described for our purposes here by Bourdieu as
systems of durable, transposable dispositions, structured structures predisposed to function as structuring structures, that is, as principles which generate and organize practices and representations that can be objectively adapted to their outcomes without presupposing a conscious aiming at ends or an express mastery of the operations necessary in order to attain them. (Bordieu, The Logic of Practice (Richard Nice (trans), Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 53)
But perhaps better understood as perception rationalizing technique that establish self-reflective iterative systems that are related to the body (and more so in contemporary identitarian stances). It is, in fact, yet another manifestation of the now ancient rational project (contemporaneously still within the lenbenswelt of the Enlightenment from its 18th century formulations) within which the possibilities and instrumentalization of critique finds its utility (utility itself being an essence, a lubricant, of the Enlightenment world view). Marcel Mauss, in his 1934 «Les techniques du corps» perhaps captured it best:
J'appelle technique un acte traditionnel efficace (et vous voyez qu'en ceci il n'est pas différent de l'acte magique, religieux, symbolique). Il faut qu'il soit traditionnel et efficace. Il n'y a pas de technique et pas de transmission, s'il n'y a pas de tradition. C'est en quoi l'homme se distingue avant tout des animaux : par la transmission de ses techniques et très probablement par leur transmission orale (Ibid., p. 9). * * * C'est grâce à la société qu'il y a une intervention de la conscience. Ce n'est pas grâce à l'inconscience qu'il y a une intervention de la société. C'est grâce à la société qu'il y a sûreté des mouvements prêts, domination du conscient sur l'émotion et l'inconscience. C'est par raison que la marine française obligera ses matelots à apprendre à nager. (Ibid., p. 22). I call technique an effective traditional act (and you see that in this it is no different from the magical, religious, symbolic act). It must be traditional and effective. There is no technique and no transmission, if there is no tradition. This is how man distinguishes himself above all from animals: by the transmission of his techniques and very probably by their oral transmission (p.9) * * * It is thanks to society that there is an intervention of conscience. It is not thanks to unconsciousness that there is an intervention of society. It is thanks to society that there is safety of ready movements, domination of the conscious over emotion and unconsciousness. It is by reason that the French navy will oblige its sailors to learn to swim. (p.22).
And, indeed, the question of critique, in all of its (vain)glorious manifestations. might be said to revolve around the question that Mauss refers to--ought the French navy to teach its sailors to swim? It may be humane to permit sailors to drawn quickly when a ship sinks or they are thrown overboard; the critique posits the opposite it is more humane to teach them to swim to extend the time for rescue and give them a chance to survive. In both cases the operative principle is humane treatment; technology, culture, expectations, and institutional operation change the rest. Fundamental critique on the other hand might suggest that the Navy ought to be operated through ships without sailors (modern technology many make that possible) or that losing sailors at sea suggests the brutality of naval warfare that ought to be avoided. This is the patterned cyclicity within which critique feels most at home. The only interesting issue is the way that critique presents itself (differently) within its local characteristics and as a function of the stage of historical development in which is appears.
Pix credit here |
The first points toward the social collective ("First, the key would be to have the concept of society at the center." (Ibid.). That parallels the discourse of modern Chinese Marxist-Leninism and runs counter to much of the discourse, for example, around human rights. But there has been a tension in liberal democratic cultures around the relationship between individual autonomy (and its rights based tropes) with that of social rights (and its emerging sustainability tropes). This remains unresolved.
Pix credit here |
The third nods in the direction of the fundamental reordering of critique from its Marxist economic foundations to contemporary identity-identitarian tropes ("Third, the semantics of class linked to the economic system would have to be replaced by a study of inclusion/exclusion into the broad variety of social roles individuals find themselves confronted with as citizens, consumers, employees, nature-lovers, partners of intimacy, social media users and so forth." Ibid.) . The object is still utilitarian in an Enlightenment sense; the question, and the space for critique, however, would inhabit the realms of value.
Pix credit here |
Kjaer's fifth theme is among the most intriguing--the elevation of the value of time as (a/the) principle marker of value ("Fifth, the only overarching ‘currency’, i.e. capital, in society would be time."). Time has always been an element of valuation; now it might displace other objects as the referent (from the "gold standard" to the "time standard"). Certainly descriptive and predictive analytics already point in the direction of time as the ordering element of value. And our own literature suggests that eventually it may be the only object against which humanity (collectively and individually) can measure "things."
On that basis, Kjaer invests a tremendous amount of expectation in the enterprise of law ("Sixth, departing from the insight that social processes and society at large consist of time and nothing else means that law only can be transformative." Ibid.). I do not share that view and it is not clear to me that law is suitable as an instrument of transformation. Yet one can take Kjaer's point that as a function of time law can only be transformative. Still, law has tended to be as much a memory of the past as it can be a gateway toward a future. And transformative instruments tend to be the tools that can be utilized by those resisting transformations through law imposed by whatever vanguard of social forces seeks to use them. An old story certainly. Law as authentically transformative, however, is worth exploring in the context of a time-value system.
As a function of the centrality of time, and its necessary fluidity, Kjaer would also "ditch" identity based critics (and its inversion in the form of the so-called identitarian movement) ("Seventh, the focus on time and the fluidity it implies means that the notion of ‘identity’ would have to be ditched altogether."Ibid.). And yet fluidity and temporality does not necessarily eliminate the power of identity, or counter-identity, so much as make the concepts fluid; indeed the emerging theories of gender fluidity already point in that direction. That approach can be generalized. The notions of temporality and fluidity has long been the stuff of phenomenology and the post-modern; it has become critical to the transformation of social relations, not through a transformative law but through the inevitable consequences of the move from the natural to the virtual realms and from observed to virtual cognition (my exploration of these concepts in The
Soulful Machine, the Virtual Person, and the “Human” Condition: An
Encounter with Jan M. Broekman, Knowledge in Change: The Semiotics of
Cognition and Conversion (Cham, Switzerland: Springer Nature, 2023)). Nonetheless, the idea is powerful in the sense that generality must in some sense produce collective solidarity that flattens the performance of identity as a political construct and as a means of organizing hierarchies within collectives.
Pix credit here |
The ninth insight returns us to the phenomenological challenge of any new ordering ("Nine, in an overall manner, the social world consists of two worlds the factually existing world and the contra-factually, equally real, normative world. Bridging the gap between them is the function of constitutions, public or private, state or societal." Ibid.). Again, an ancient challenge; yet it is one that lends itself nicely to the sort of dialectics for which European society once had developed a great capacity to utilize effectively. Time concepts are critical here to Kjaer's conceptual universe: normative instruments create ordering parameters rather than foxed barriers. In virtual space this is easier to conceive.Yet any shift in emphasis within the normative/experiental binary can substantially change the context in which dialectics occurs; and one still requires to overcome the Nietzschean issue of the corrupting effect of a priestly caste overseeing any such dialectics.
Pix credit here |
For Kjaer, the death of critique born of the exuberance and horror of the post 1945 era serves as a doorway back to the theater of reflexive encounters with cognition and its social constructs. New times, different show.
The Frankfurt School of Critical Theory and the US-American critical legal studies movement are now defunct and will not come back to life. A new theory is needed. One where the concept of critique is integrated playing is role as a part of a broader theoretical architecture. * * * Hence, performing critique is the opposite of ideology. Critique is not about pushing through a particular policy program, set of values or the furthering of the interests of a particular group. Rather critique is about continued self-reflection, the empathy involved in seeking to understand ‘the other’ and most importantly to engage in the cool and necessarily distant and non-emotional process of obtaining knowledge in an objective form as possible. ("What Comes After Critique, supra).Here one encounters a possible liberal democratic counter to the developing notion of self-revolution within Chinese Marxist Leninist systems. The techniques are similar even as the cognition of what is percieved varies as a function of the assumptions with which one approaches perception (see, e.g., Social Revolution (社会革命) as Self-Revolution (自我革命) and the New Quality Production of CPC Modernization: 习近平 深入推进党的自我革命 [Xi Jinping, Deepen the Party's Self-Revolution] (Part of a speech at the Third Plenary Session of the 20th Central Commission for Discipline Inspection on January 8, 2024))). A powerful critique in any case, one worthy of further development and engagement.
The essay is reposted below and may be accessed from its original publication site here.
Poul Kjaer |
What Comes After ’Critique’?
‘Critique’ seems to have run out of steam, increasingly being reduced to a ritualized performative act. ‘Of course, I am critical’ one says and goes on with everyday practice. This is most visible in the gradual fading out of the Frankfurt School of Critical Theory. Surprisingly few read Habermas today. The US-American critical legal studies movement, essentially a lightweight version of Frankfurt School insights adjusted to the US-American context and to law and combined with a dose of French poststructuralism, has suffered the same fate.
That is a curious development as ‘critique’ has been with us ever since Kant posed the question ‘What is Enlightenment?’ in 1784. Of course, there was ‘critique’ before including in Kant’s own earlier writings. But in Kant’s short manifest critique took center stage both as a philosophical doctrine and as a ‘way of life’. Hegel, topped up with an approach to society where ‘critique’ as a social practice was seen as systematically woven into the societal structure of modern society. Since then, ‘critique’ became omnipresent until our time.
One reason for the fading away of ‘critique’ is that conceptually more refined and epistemologically more powerful theoretical alternatives are out there now. That does, however, not seem to be the main reason. Rather large parts of the scholarly space and public imagination have fallen prey to group logic and identity thinking representing the antithesis to Kant’s insights and that irrespective of whether it comes in a left- or rightwing version. In both cases ‘identity’ has become the mantra in a hyper-individualized way while contradictory referring to group categories such as ‘class, gender and race’ if left-wing or ‘nation, religious heritage and traditional gender roles’ if right-wing. Considering that the concept of the individual emerged in the moment society became characterized by persons gaining multiple social roles, the most presumable reason for all the talk of identity is however that it serves as a ‘cover up’ of the increased emptying of the subject. One talks of identity in the absence of it.
The storm we are currently entering and where the worst is likely yet to come, will however end one day. Out of the wreckage of the symbolic and literal burning down of the cathedrals of reason a phoenix might however appear from the ashes in the form of a new theory of society and its progress towards reason. ‘Progress towards reason’ are big words and it is hardly possible to write them without a certain degree of irony. The day the cathedrals of reason are burning for real the irony is, however, likely to disappear.
But how could a new theory look like? And what role would law play in it? Essentially it would be a renewed and transformed theory of modernity. ‘Modernity’ is another big word and possibly the least fashionable word of our time. The least cool person at the party is likely to be the one still believing in ‘modernity’. Possibly an economist who works for the IMF.
Modernity has its dark side. The holocaust was also part of modernity as Zygmunt Bauman made clear. The extension of logics of modernity through colonialism is another clear example, just as Kierkegaard’s exploration of existential fear reflected a modern way of life. Hence, the concept of modernity, as already argued by Hegel, should include its own self-reflection concerning its dark side. A self-reflection that could be used as a springboard to recast the concept. ‘Modernity in the Twenty First Century’ could be the title of the book.
First, the key would be to have the concept of society at the center. The dominant structural liberalist legal and non-legal discourses of the past 50 years did not have a concept of society, only of individuals. The twin epistemes of ‘human rights law’ and ‘law and economics’ are here the cases in point. Ditching this epistemic setup would be the first step. But it would have to be replaced with a theory of society which has coherency as its core focus point. Georg Simmel’s classical sociological question concerning ‘how society is possible?’ would have to be front and center. Questions of coherency between those with higher education and those not, between cities and rural areas or between generations, planetary boundaries and so forth. This does not mean that the concept of the individual has no relevance, only that individuals are considered social beings and that their fulfillment primarily is to be found outside and not inside themselves. Hence, a change of perspective is needed as today’s mental health pandemic tend to be treated as a primarily psychological rather than a sociological issue.
Second, a society which only can be conceived of as a world society (Weltgesellschaft) or in English parlance a global society. The core element of practical regulation would often be one of regulating global public goods, be it in relation to artificial intelligence, climate, pandemic responses or value chains or any other matter with global relevance.
Third, the semantics of class linked to the economic system would have to be replaced by a study of inclusion/exclusion into the broad variety of social roles individuals find themselves confronted with as citizens, consumers, employees, nature-lovers, partners of intimacy, social media users and so forth. Social roles which all have their different logics, forms of capital and values. Consumer law, labor law, environmental law, family law, digital law etc. would have to find ways to conceive of the particular social role they seek to regulate in a sustainable way.
Fourth, the concept of rights would have to be reformulated. The dominant narrative of political, economic and social rights is one of private rights. The right to property is here the case in point. While the individual dimension is certainly important the broader societal function of rights is equally important. Property rights not only aim to secure individual freedom but also demarcates the private and public spheres of society. While the private/public distinction can be considered as artificially constructed, volatile and factually full of contradictions and grey-zones and in need of constant renegotiation it nonetheless serves as an ordering principle. Taxation, a condition for public institutions to thrive, would for example not be possible without the demarcation of private property through rights as it’s the granting of private rights which makes them taxable.
Fifth, the only overarching ‘currency’, i.e. capital, in society would be time. Sustainability implies durability over time. But social processes always move and there is always fluidity of time. The battles to be fought are largely battles over time. Digital time, working time, time for intimacy and so forth. The family lawyer deals with how much time separated parents should enjoy with the child caught in-between, the environmental lawyer with the time of decomposition of a chemical substance in the ground and the human rights lawyer with the maximum detention time of a person withheld by the authorities.
Sixth, departing from the insight that social processes and society at large consist of time and nothing else means that law only can be transformative. Law upholds normative expectations and is as such ‘conservative’ in nature. But norms move too. They also change over time. They only do so at a slower pace than the cognitive stirred social processes such as economy, science and technology driving society forward through constant creative destruction. Transformative law is therefore confronted with the task of simultaneously stabilizing and changing social processes in the same operation.
Seventh, the focus on time and the fluidity it implies means that the notion of ‘identity’ would have to be ditched altogether. In the modern world there is no such thing as a stable identity. Life rather consists of a constant juggling of a multitude of partly overlapping and partly contradictory expectations and social roles with those roles themselves being constantly renegotiated. Hence in contrast to the idea of law merely stabilizing expectations and social roles the law should rather be conceived of as a facilitator of constant redefinition and realignment both acting as a stable framework and as a catalyst for change in the never-ending processes of individuals and social formations reinventing themselves on a day-to-day basis.
Eight, the idea of ‘groups’ and group rights would have to be sidetracked as well. The disaster which grew out of the interwar period was intrinsically linked to the atomizing of society along group lines in the form of ‘social classes’, ‘races’, ‘religious congregations’ and so forth. Today’s left- and right-wing categories of ‘class, gender and race’ and ‘nation, religious heritage and traditional gender roles’ threatens to led society down a similar track. Legal scholarship needs to avoid the temptation of contributing to the construction of such groups. One way of doing so is to advance the study of the legal history of the instrumentalization of law for group building purposes and that both in in regard to the capture of law by powerful groups and the use of law for marginalization purposes through the exclusionary construction of disadvantaged groups.
Nine, in an overall manner, the social world consists of two worlds the factually existing world and the contra-factually, equally real, normative world. Bridging the gap between them is the function of constitutions, public or private, state or societal. Constitutions are drift anchors. Not anchors lowered to the seabed to fixate the ship in a specific position but anchors that drift with the societal ship as it moves in order to stabilize it in the process. Hence a new concept of constitutionalisation is needed with constitutionalisation understood as a continued process not fixated in a singular constitution or constitutional moment.
Ten, all this will however not be possible without a profound recasting of the legal discipline and legal education. Doctrinal law skills, while necessary, provide an insufficient toolbox for addressing the problem constellations of the 21st century. In the constant battle of hegemony between professions, theologians, philosophers, lawyers and in the last fifty years economists have all had their peak period. Without change the still ongoing strategic downgrading of the centrality of the legal profession in society will continue. In scholarly terms that means that a far more offensive approach is needed. Over the past fifth years insights from other disciplines, especially economics but also anthropology, political science, psychology and sociology among others have invaded legal scholarship. Law and economics, for example, ask how legal problems can be solved with (micro-)economic methods. But maybe one should also ask how economic problems can be solved with legal methods?
On the above background one might return to question of the future of ‘critique’. The Frankfurt School of Critical Theory and the US-American critical legal studies movement are now defunct and will not come back to life. A new theory is needed. One where the concept of critique is integrated playing is role as a part of a broader theoretical architecture.
In its broader societal form, critique as a constant act of reflexivity of society also needs to be brought back to a constructive form with mass media law and regulation here playing a central role. Following Kant, critique is an art form requiring skills, education and utmost levels of self-discipline. Hence, performing critique is the opposite of ideology. Critique is not about pushing through a particular policy program, set of values or the furthering of the interests of a particular group. Rather critique is about continued self-reflection, the empathy involved in seeking to understand ‘the other’ and most importantly to engage in the cool and necessarily distant and non-emotional process of obtaining knowledge in an objective form as possible. A strive for objectivity which never can be fully reached but which one can come closer to by taking as many epistemological points of observation as possible into consideration. Constant epistemological alteration rather than one-dimensionality is the key approach. Sapere aude! Dare to know as Kant put it.
(Photo: Andrew Charney)
No comments:
Post a Comment